Skip navigation
The Habeas Citebook: Prosecutorial Misconduct - Header

Fordham University School of Law, Prosecutors and Professional Regulation, 2012

Download original document:
Brief thumbnail
This text is machine-read, and may contain errors. Check the original document to verify accuracy.
Fordham University
School of Law

November 2012
Prosecutors and Professional Regulation
By
BRUCE A. GREEN
LOUIS STEIN PROFESSOR OF LAW AND DIRECTOR,
LOUIS STEIN CENTER FOR LAW AND ETHICS
25 Georgetown Journal of Law and Ethics 873 (2012)
This paper can be downloaded without charge
from the Social Science Research Network electronic library:
http://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

Electronic
Electroniccopy
copyavailable
availableat:
at:https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252
http://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

ARTICLES
Prosecutors and Professional Regulation
BRUCE A. GREEN*
Much is expected of prosecutors. The bench and bar take the view that
prosecutors are “ministers of justice”1 with a responsibility to uphold higher
professional standards than other lawyers,2 and prosecutors generally agree.3
But not so much is required of them. Few professional conduct provisions
specifically target their work,4 and those provisions are mostly unde---* Louis Stein Professor, Fordham University School of Law; Director, Stein Center for Law and Ethics. This
article focuses on three recent matters with which I had some professional involvement and/or personal
familiarity, principally through my bar association activities. I have endeavored, perhaps not with full success,
to bring as much objectivity and balance to the article as possible. © 2012, Bruce A. Green.
For generous comments on earlier drafts, I am particularly grateful to Jim Brudney, David Luban, Daniel
Medwed, Russ Pearce, Ian Weinstein, Ellen Yaroshefsky, and Ben Zipursky, and I express thanks to my
Fordham colleagues who asked probing questions at the faculty workshop in which I presented an earlier draft.
1. See, e.g., Berger v. United States, 295 U.S. 78, 88 (1935) (stating that prosecutors have special obligations
as representatives “not of an ordinary party to a controversy, but of a sovereignty whose obligation to govern
impartially is as compelling as its obligation to govern at all; and whose interest, therefore, in a criminal
prosecution is not that it shall win a case, but that justice shall be done.”); MODEL RULES OF PROF’L CONDUCT R.
3.8, cmt. 1 (2010) [hereinafter MODEL RULES] (“A prosecutor has the responsibility of a minister of justice and
not simply that of an advocate. This responsibility carries with it specific obligations to see that the defendant is
accorded procedural justice, that guilt is decided upon the basis of sufficient evidence, and that special
precautions are taken to prevent and to rectify the conviction of innocent persons.”). See generally Bruce A.
Green, Why Should Prosecutors “Seek Justice”?, 26 FORDHAM URB. L.J. 609 (1999).
2. See, e.g., People v. Jones, 44 N.Y.2d 76, 81 (1978) (“[T]he responsibilities of a prosecutor for fairness and
open-dealing are of a higher magnitude than those of a private litigant . . . .”); N.Y.S. BAR COMM. ON PROF’L
ETHICS, Op. 683 (1996) ([“The prosecutor’s] ‘quasi-judicial function’ implies special professional obligations
that set prosecutors apart from other lawyers.”).
3. See, e.g., NATIONAL DISTRICT ATTORNEYS ASSOCIATION, NATIONAL PROSECUTION STANDARDS 1-1.1 (3d ed.
2009):
The prosecutor is an independent administrator of justice. The primary responsibility of a prosecutor
is to seek justice, which can only be achieved by the representation and presentation of the truth. This
responsibility includes, but is not limited to, ensuring that the guilty are held accountable, that the
innocent are protected from unwarranted harm, and that the rights of all participants, particularly
victims of crime, are respected.
4. See ANGELA J. DAVIS, ARBITRARY JUSTICE: THE POWER OF THE AMERICAN PROSECUTOR 150-51 (2007)
(“[M]odel rule 3.8 does not adequately address the conduct and behavior of prosecutors . . . . The rule’s
inadequacy lies not only in its failure to address critical issues but in the vagueness of its language.”); Bruce A.
Green, Prosecutorial Ethics as Usual, 2003 U. ILL. L. REV. 1573.

873

Electronic
Electroniccopy
copyavailable
availableat:
at:https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252
http://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

874

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

manding.5 Courts often interpret the generally applicable rules of professional
conduct as less restrictively applied to prosecutors than to other lawyers.6 When
prosecutors engage in questionable conduct that does implicate professional
conduct rules, professional discipline rarely follows.7 For every case in which a
prosecutor is publicly sanctioned for egregious misconduct,8 there are many
more in which prosecutors’ questionable conduct goes unpunished.9 Although
the U.S. Supreme Court, in recognizing prosecutorial immunity, assumed that
prosecutors are adequately policed by regulators of the bar,10 in reality, there is no
reason for prosecutors to fear professional regulation:11 in making, interpreting,
---5. See Green, supra note 4, at 1587-96.
6. See Fred C. Zacharias & Bruce A. Green, The Uniqueness of Federal Prosecutors, 88 GEO. L.J. 207,
228-35 (2000) (discussing exemptions of prosecutors from ethical restrictions relating to investigations, witness
compensation, and conflicts of interest).
7. See Edward M. Genson & Marc W. Martin, The Epidemic of Prosecutorial Courtroom Misconduct in
Illinois: Is it Time to Start Prosecuting the Prosecutors?, 19 LOY. U. CHI. L.J. 39, 47 (1987); Bruce A. Green,
Policing Federal Prosecutors: Do Too Many Regulators Produce Too Little Enforcement?, 8 ST. THOMAS L.
REV. 69 (1995) [hereinafter Policing Federal Prosecutors]; David Keenan et al., The Myth of Prosecutorial
Accountability After Connick v. Thompson: Why Current Professional Responsibility Measures Cannot Protect
Against Prosecutorial Misconduct, YALE L.J. (2011), http://yale.academia.edu/DavidKeenan/Papers/1089349/
The_Myth_of_Prosecutorial_Accountability_After_Connick_v._Thompson_Why_Existing_Professional_
Responsibility_Measures_Cannot_Protect_Against_Prosecutorial_Misconduct; Ellen Yaroshefsky, Wrongful
Convictions: It Is Time to Take Prosecution Discipline Seriously, 8 UDC/DCSL L. REV. 275 (2004); Fred C.
Zacharias & Bruce A. Green, The Duty to Avoid Wrongful Convictions: A Thought Experiment in the Regulation
of Prosecutors, 89 B.U. L. REV. 1, 4 n.9 (2009) (citing authority on ineffectiveness of discipline of prosecutors);
Fred C. Zacharias, The Professional Discipline of Prosecutors, 79 N.C.L. REV. 721 (2001). There is evidence
that internal regulatory mechanisms are equally deferential. See Joel B. Rudin, The Supreme Court Assumes
Errant Prosecutors Will Be Disciplined by Their Offices or the Bar: Three Case Studies that Prove that
Assumption Wrong, 80 FORDHAM L. REV. 537 (2011); see also Bruce A. Green, Regulating Federal Prosecutors:
Let There Be Light, 118 YALE L.J. Pocket Part 156 (Supp. 2009) [hereinafter Regulating Federal Prosecutors]
(discussing failure of the U.S. Department of Justice to make its individual disciplinary determinations public).
8. See Zacharias & Green, supra note 7, at 12 (“Durham, North Carolina District Attorney Mike Nifong’s
disbarment in June 2007 was an exceptional instance in which disciplinary regulators imposed meaningful
sanctions [for prosecutorial misconduct].”).
9. See, e.g., In re Special Proceedings, 2011 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 133812 (D.D.C. Nov. 21, 2011) (declining to
initiate criminal contempt proceedings against federal prosecutors who disregarded discovery obligations in
prosecution of Senator Ted Stevens); In re Auerhahn, 2011 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 104717 (D. Mass. Sept. 15, 2011)
(declining to discipline federal prosecutor for disregarding discovery obligations); Rudin, supra note 7.
10. See Connick v. Thompson, 131 S. Ct. 1350, 1362-63 (2011) (stating that as an attorney, a prosecutor
“who violates his or her ethical obligations is subject to professional discipline, including sanctions, suspension,
and disbarment”); Imbler v. Pachtman, 424 U.S. 409, 429 (1976) (“A prosecutor stands perhaps unique, among
officials whose acts could deprive persons of constitutional rights, in his amenability to professional discipline
by an association of his peers”). For a recent refutation of this assumption, see Rudin, supra note 7. For a general
critique of prosecutorial immunity, see Margaret Z. Johns, Unsupportable and Unjustified: A Critique of
Absolute Prosecutorial Immunity, 80 FORDHAM L. REV. 509 (2011).
11. Stephanos Bibas, Prosecutorial Regulation Versus Prosecutorial Accountability, 157 U. PA. L. REV. 959,
962 (2009) (“The potential for abuse of discretion calls for more effective mechanisms to oversee and regulate
prosecutors’ conduct. Many, if not most, other government actors enjoy less power yet are subject to far more
regulation than prosecutors are. The comparison suggests that prosecutors are the outliers and that some new
regulatory mechanisms are likely to be worth the cost.”); Ellen Yaroshefsky & Bruce A. Green, Prosecutors’
Ethics in Context: Influences on Prosecutorial Disclosure, in Leslie Levin & Lynn Mather, LAWYERS IN

Electronic
Electroniccopy
copyavailable
availableat:
at:https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252
http://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

875

and enforcing rules of professional conduct, the legal profession’s regulators are
highly deferential to them.12
Even so, prosecutors often express mistrust of professional regulators, their
rules, and their processes. Twenty years ago, prosecutors’ mistrust may have
been more understandable. Prosecutors perceived, probably unfairly, that the
organized bar had been captured by defense lawyers who were seeking to use
professional regulation to impose limits on criminal investigative authority that
the law did not otherwise recognize. Today, this perception is even further from
the reality, but it has persisted in the rhetoric prosecutors employ in discourse
regarding their professional conduct, even in contexts such as rule-making where
prosecutors are not representing one side in an adversary process but purport to
express personal views. This article explores prosecutors’ public attitude toward
professional regulation, beginning with a brief account of their responses to
perceived over-regulation two decades ago, then offering three recent illustrations, and finally exploring the significance of prosecutors’ rhetorical challenges
to external regulatory efforts. It suggests that the rhetoric reflects a departure
from prosecutors’ professional obligation to act in the public interest and that the
rhetoric may have various negative repercussions, including a likely negative
impact on the culture of prosecutors’ offices.13

I. A BRIEF MODERN HISTORY
Regulation of the bar in the United States has principally been the province of
state courts, which admit lawyers to practice in their states, adopt professional
conduct rules to govern those lawyers, and oversee the disciplinary processes
used to sanction members of the state bar who violate the rules.14 Federal courts
have the authority to establish professional conduct rules governing lawyers—
including prosecutors—in federal litigation, but they largely rely on state-court
rules and state-court disciplinary processes.15 State courts in turn rely substan-

PRACTICE: ETHICAL DECISION MAKING IN CONTEXT 289 (2012) (concluding that “[p]otential civil and criminal
liability and professional discipline play little or no role” in influencing prosecutors’ decisions regarding
disclosures to the defense).
12. Professional regulators might be deferential to prosecutors for various reasons, including that they are
confident in the ability of prosecutors’ offices to regulate themselves and that they are reluctant to engage in
confrontations with politically powerful prosecutors’ offices. See Zacharias & Green, supra note 7, at 52-57
(2009) (discussing why disciplinary agencies would be reluctant to proceed against prosecutors who act
incompetently).
13. This is not to suggest that prosecutors have a monopoly on rhetorical excess—they do not. See, e.g.,
Alafair Burke, Talking About Prosecutors, 31 CARDOZO L. REV. 2019 (2010).
14. State courts’ regulatory role is far from exclusive, however. See James M. Fischer, External Control over
the American Bar, 19 GEO. J. LEGAL ETHICS 59, 60 (2006); Ted Schneyer, An Interpretation of Recent
Developments in the Regulation of Law Practice, 30 OKLA. CITY U. L. REV. 559, 566 (2005); Fred C. Zacharias,
The Myth of Self-Regulation, 93 MINN. L. REV. 1147 (2009).
15. See generally Bruce A. Green & Fred C. Zacharias, Regulating Federal Prosecutors’ Ethics, 55 VAND. L.
REV. 381 (2002).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

876

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

tially on the work product of the American Bar Association (“ABA”) in setting
standards of professional conduct.16
The ABA has evolved over time since its late nineteenth century origin as a
representative of the professional elite.17 Today, it has over 400,000 members and
seeks to speak on behalf of the entire U.S. legal profession to promote the good of
the profession and public.18 Since its inception, a principal objective has been to
articulate, codify and promote professional standards for lawyers and judges.19
Although most of the ABA’s model professional conduct rules are written for
lawyers generally, they have always reflected the prevailing understanding that
lawyers serving as prosecutors have a unique professional role that implicates
special professional responsibilities.20 The current codification, the Model Rules
of Professional Conduct,21 includes various provisions applicable to all lawyers
including prosecutors, but also includes one provision, Model Rule 3.8, which is
specifically directed at prosecutors, as did the 1970 Model Code of Professional
Responsibility22 and, before that, the 1908 Canons of Professional Ethics.23
However, the prosecutorial ethics rule in the 1970 Model Code included only two
---16. See Fred C. Zacharias & Bruce A. Green, Rationalizing Judicial Regulation of Lawyers, 70 OHIO ST. L.J.
73, 110-11 (2009) (suggesting that “[t]o avoid capture by the bar, or the appearance of capture, state supreme
courts need to involve themselves more fully than they traditionally have in the code-drafting process”).
Although the ABA is a private professional association, prosecutors have acknowledged that “in some respects
[it has] served as a quasi-governmental entity” and “has been permitted to play a unique role in the development
of law,” and that its model professional conduct rules in particular “have traditionally won strong acceptance in
the legal, judicial, and political communities . . . due in no small part to the widely held belief that the rules are a
consensus product of many decades of dedicated and thoughtful attention to problems in legal ethics.”
Prosecutors and the ABA, A Report to the President of the ABA by the Advisory Committee on the Prosecution
Function (Jan. 8, 1992) at 11, 15 (on file with the author).
17. See generally Jerold S. Auerbach, UNEQUAL JUSTICE: LAWYERS AND SOCIAL CHANGE IN AMERICA (1976).
18. The ABA currently describes its mission as “[t]o serve equally our members, our profession and the
public by defending liberty and delivering justice as the national representative of the legal profession.”
See Advocacy, A.B.A., http://www.americanbar.org/advocacy.html (last visited June 3, 2012). Although the
Association seeks a membership and leadership that are broadly representative of the profession, that does not
guarantee that the public interest is not outweighed by the interests of subgroups within the profession or of the
profession as a whole. See generally Elizabeth Chambliss & Bruce A. Green, Some Realism About Bar
Associations, 57 DEPAUL L. REV. 425, 430-47 (2008) (discussing why viewpoint diversity may not mitigate the
effect of professional self-interest on the formulation of bar association policies).
19. See generally Auerbach, supra note 17, at 40-53.
20. This understanding predates the adoption of the 1908 Canons. See, e.g., Rush v. Cavanaugh, 2 Pa. 187
(Pa. 1845) (“[The prosecutor] is expressly bound by his official oath to behave himself in his office of attorney
with all due fidelity to the court as well as the client; and he violates it when he consciously presses for an unjust
judgment: much more so when he presses for the conviction of an innocent man”). For discussions of Rush v.
Cavenaugh, see Russell G. Pearce, Rediscovering the Republican Origins of the Legal Ethics Codes, 6 GEO. J.
LEGAL ETHICS 241, 257-58 (1992); Fred C. Zacharias & Bruce A. Green, Reconceptualizing Advocacy Ethics,
74 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 1 (2005).
21. MODEL RULES.
22. MODEL CODE OF PROF’L RESPONSIBILITY DR 7-103 (1983) [hereinafter MODEL CODE].
23. CANONS OF PROF’L ETHICS 5 (1908) (“The primary duty of a lawyer engaged in public prosecution is not
to convict, but to see that justice is done. The suppression of facts or the secreting of witnesses capable of
establishing the innocence of the accused is highly reprehensible.”).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

877

subsections: one codifying the duty to refrain from prosecuting in the absence
of probable cause,24 and the other requiring prosecutors to disclose favorable
evidence to the defense.25 Although Model Rule 3.8 includes several new subsections, it still covers a relatively narrow range of issues.26
Since the 1960s, the ABA has sought to provide further guidance to
prosecutors as well as criminal defense lawyers by developing Standards of
Criminal Justice addressing a considerably broader range of ethical questions
that arise in criminal cases. The drafting process has been ongoing and, to date,
the ABA has issued more than twenty sets of Standards, many of which have
undergone significant revisions. The current Standards are the product of a
thorough process that engages prosecutors, defense lawyers, judges, and their
institutional representatives.27 Unlike the Model Rules, the Standards are not
designed to be adopted by courts as enforceable rules, but rather to codify a
professional consensus among prosecutors, defense lawyers, and judges about
how lawyers and others should behave in criminal cases. As the Supreme Court
has recognized, courts may look to Standards selectively for assistance in
---24. MODEL CODE DR 7-103(A). The provision was carried over into Model Rule 3.8(a). There are
exceedingly few published decisions disciplining prosecutors for knowingly initiating criminal charges without
probable cause. A recent one involves the Maricopa County Attorney and his deputy who, a disciplinary judge
found, engaged in a course of prosecutorial misconduct and other professional abuses warranting disbarment, of
which filing charges without probable cause was scarcely the most serious. Opinion and Order Imposing
Sanctions, Matter of Thomas, PDJ-2011-9022 (Ariz. Apr. 10, 2012). Several other decisions invoking the
probable-cause rule have involved Iowa prosecutors who, with the knowledge and approval of the trial judge,
allowed defendants charged with more serious crimes (as to which there was probable cause) to plead guilty to
minor traffic offenses that had no relationship to the defendants’ alleged conduct. See Iowa Supreme Ct. Att’y
Disciplinary Bd. v. Borth, 728 N.W.2d 205 (Iowa 2007); Iowa Supreme Ct. Att’y Disciplinary Bd. v. Zenor, 707
N.W.2d 176 (Iowa 2005); Iowa Supreme Ct. Att’y Disciplinary Bd. v. Howe, 706 N.W.2d 360 (Iowa 2005).
Evidently, the practice condemned by the Iowa Supreme Court in these decisions is openly undertaken in many
other states. See Mari Byrne, Note, Baseless Pleas: A Mockery of Justice, 78 FORDHAM L. REV. 2961 (2010).
Another case, In re Leonhardt, 930 P.2d 844 (Or. 1997), involved an Oregon prosecutor who secured a grand
jury indictment of police officers based on her own unsworn statements, without presenting any witnesses or
other evidence. The evidence suggested that her unsworn statements were fabricated. She subsequently covered
up the deficiency of the indictments by falsifying grand jury records and lying to the court, leading to her
criminal conviction on multiple counts of forgery and tampering with public records. She was then disbarred for
a slew of disciplinary violations, including causing criminal charges to be instituted when she knew or it was
obvious that the charges were not supported by probable cause. In several other cases, disciplinary charges were
brought but not sustained. See Att’y Grievance Comm’n v. Gansler, 835 A.2d 548, 573-74 (Md. 2003); In re
Burrows, 629 P.2d 820, 826 (Or. 1981); In re Lucareli, 611 N.W.2d 754 (Wis. 2000).
25. MODEL CODE DR 7-103(B).
26. See Green, supra note 4, at 1575.
27. For discussions of the drafting process, see Kenneth J. Hodson, The American Bar Association Standards
for Criminal Justice: Their Development, Evolution, and Future, 59 DENV. U. L.J. 3 (1981); Rory K. Little, The
ABA’s Project to Revise the Prosecution and Defense Function Standards, 62 HASTINGS L.J. 1113 (2011);
Rory K. Little, The Role of Reporter for a Law Project, 4 HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 747 (2011). The Standards on
the Prosecution and Defense Function are currently under revision. For collections of articles on the works in
progress, see Symposium: Roundtable Discussion of the ABA’s Standards for Criminal Litigation, 38 HASTINGS
CONST. L.Q. no. 4 (2011); A Discourse on the ABA’s Criminal Justice Standards: Prosecution and Defense
Functions, 62 HASTINGS L.J. no. 5 (2011).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

878

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

ascertaining what is expected of a professionally competent lawyer.28
In the 1980s and early 1990s, several conflicts erupted regarding professional
conduct rules and standards that influenced prosecutors’ current attitudes. The
disagreements related primarily to prosecutors’ investigative conduct, particularly in federal cases.
The most pitched battle was over the application of the “no-contact” rules,29
which restrict all lawyers and their agents from communicating with represented
parties.30 Defense lawyers sought to invoke these rules in criminal cases as a
ground for suppressing admissions made by represented defendants in the course
of undercover investigations and interviews by investigators and informants
acting under prosecutors’ direction.31 In response, the Department of Justice
(“DOJ”) adopted an administrative regulation meant to exempt prosecutors from
the no-contact rules and to substitute a more liberal standard.32 Congress, in turn,
adopted legislation known as the McDade Amendment that superseded the DOJ
regulation and subjected federal prosecutors to state professional conduct rules.33
---28. See Strickland v. Washington, 466 U.S. 668, 688-89 (1984) (“Prevailing norms of practice as reflected
in American Bar Association standards and the like, e.g., ABA Standards for Criminal Justice 4-1.1 to 4-8.6
(2d ed. 1980) (‘The Defense Function’), are guides to determining what is reasonable, but they are only guides.
No particular set of detailed rules for counsel’s conduct can satisfactorily take account of the variety of
circumstances faced by defense counsel or the range of legitimate decisions regarding how best to represent a
criminal defendant.”).
29. These are state professional conduct rules, based on Model Rule 4.2 or Disciplinary Rule 7-104 of the
predecessor Model Code, which restrict lawyers and their surrogates from communicating with represented
persons (including representatives of represented entities) regarding the subject of the representation.
30. See generally Roger C. Cramton & Lisa K. Udell, State Ethics Rules and Federal Prosecutors: The
Controversies over the Anti-Contact and Subpoena Rules, 53 U. PITT. L. REV. 291 (1992); Bruce A. Green,
Whose Rules of Professional Conduct Should Govern Lawyers in Federal Court and How Should the Rules Be
Created?, 64 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 460, 470-82 (1996); Neil Salon, Note, Prosecutors and Model Rule 4.2: An
Examination of Appropriate Remedies, 12 GEO. J. LEGAL ETHICS 393 (1999); F. Dennis Saylor, IV & J. Douglas
Wilson, The Application of Model Rule 4.2 to Federal Prosecutors, 53 U. PITT. L. REV. 459 (1992).
31. See, e.g., United States v. Hammad, 858 F.2d 834 (2d Cir. 1988). See generally Bruce A. Green, A
Prosecutor’s Communications With Represented Defendants: What Are the Limits?, 24 CRIM. L. BULL. 283
(1988) (discussing cases).
32. 28 C.F.R. 77.10(a) (1998) (“Communications With Represented Persons”). For commentary on this
controversial regulation, see Jennifer Marie Buettner, Compromising Professionalism: The Justice Department’s Anti-Contact Rule, 23 J. LEGAL PROF. 121 (1999); Alafair S.R. Burke, Note, Reconciling Professional
Ethics and Prosecutorial Power: The No-Contact Rule Debate, 46 STAN. L. REV. 1635 (1994); Neals-Erik
William Delker, Ethics and the Federal Prosecutor: The Continuing Conflict Over the Application of Model
Rule 4.2 to Federal Attorneys, 44 AM. U. L. REV. 855 (1995); Green, supra note 30, at 473-82; Jocelyn Lupert,
Note, The Department of Justice Rule Governing Communications With Represented Persons: Has the
Department Defied Ethics?, 46 SYRACUSE L. REV. 1119 (1996); Todd S. Schulman, Note, Wisdom Without
Power: The Department of Justice’s Attempt to Exempt Federal Prosecutors from State No-Contact Rules,
71 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1067 (1996); Robert Sneed, The “No-Contact” Rule and Prosecutorial Misconduct,
47 S.C. L. REV. 130 (1995); Richard M. Zanfardino, Leveling the Playing Field for Federal Prosecutors or an
End Around Ethics? An Evaluation of the Thornburgh Memorandum and the Reno Rule, 43 NAVAL L. REV. 137
(1996).
33. Citizens Protection Act (“McDade Amendment”), Pub. L. No. 105-277, div. A, Sec. 101(b), § 801(a),
112 Stat. 2681 (1998) (codified in relevant part at 28 U.S.C. § 530B (2000)). For discussions of this law, see
Gregory B. LeDonne, Revisiting the McDade Amendment: Finding the Appropriate Solution for the Federal

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

879

The controversy over no-contact rules was largely resolved by federal decisions
interpreting them to permit undercover investigations that comport with the
Constitution.34
During the same time period, several other battles broke out over the
regulation of prosecutors. One was over the ABA’s adoption of a new professional conduct provision restricting prosecutors’ issuance of subpoenas to
attorneys.35 Two others involved the reach of generally applicable rules: the duty
of candor in ex parte proceedings, which might require prosecutors to disclose
exculpatory evidence to the grand jury,36 and the duty to refrain from deceitful
conduct, which might forbid prosecutors’ initiation of undercover investigations.37 Additionally, prosecutors challenged two revisions proposed in 1989 to
the ABA Prosecution Function Standards, one relating to attorneys’ subpoenas
and the other relating to forfeitures of legal fees.38
In challenging the adoption or application of professional conduct rules and
standards to restrict investigative activities by prosecutors and their agents,
federal prosecutors argued in part that the restrictions were unwarranted as a
matter of policy. In general, prosecutors argued that the rules in question, for
little public benefit, seriously interfered with prosecutors’ discretion to employ
legitimate law-enforcement investigative methods, such as undercover investigations, to uncover evidence of criminal conduct. The substantive arguments were
reasonable and respectful of the regulatory role of courts, disciplinary agencies,
and the organized bar, and they largely carried the day. But federal prosecutors
made additional assertions that appeared to challenge the basic premise that
prosecutors, as lawyers, should be subject to professional regulation.39 This line
of argument essentially stated that professional conduct rules were an illegitimate
vehicle for regulating areas of practice that are already addressed by statutes and
constitutional case law; that regulatory institutions lacked competence to take
adequate account of law enforcement interests or were potentially captive of the

Government Lawyer, 44 HARV. J. ON LEGIS. 231 (2007); Jesselyn Alicia Radack, The Big Chill: Negative Effects
of the McDade Amendment and the Conflict Between Federal Statutes, 14 GEO. J. LEGAL ETHICS 707 (2001);
Zacharias & Green, supra note 6.
34. See, e.g., United States v. Carona, 630 F.3d 917 (9th Cir. 2010).
35. See, e.g., United States v. Ferrara, 54 F.3d 825 (D.C. Cir. 1995); Whitehouse v. U.S. Dist. Court, 53 F.3d
1349 (1st Cir. 1995); Baylson v. Disciplinary Bd., 975 F.2d 102, 105 (3d Cir. 1992); Kolibash v. Comm. on
Legal Ethics, 872 F.2d 571, 575 (4th Cir. 1989). See generally Cramton & Udell, supra note 30; Fred C.
Zacharias, A Critical Look at Rules Governing Grand Jury Subpoenas of Attorneys, 76 MINN. L. REV. 917
(1992).
36. See Green & Zacharias, supra note 15, at 384 n.3. The ABA initially interpreted its rule requiring
disclosure of adverse facts in ex parte proceedings to apply to grand jury proceedings but withdrew this
interpretation when it amended the Model Rules in 2002. See id.; MODEL RULES R. 3.8 cmt.
37. See Green & Zacharias, supra note 15, at 385 n.5.
38. See Andrew Sonner, Witness for the Prosecution, 6 CRIM. JUST. 1 (Fall 1991).
39. Memorandum from Richard Thornburgh for All Justice Department Litigators Re Communications with
Persons Represented by Counsel (June 8, 1989) (unpublished office memorandum) [hereinafter Thornburgh
Memorandum], reprinted in In re Doe, 801 F. Supp. 478, 489-93 (D.N.M. 1992).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

880

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

defense bar; and that federal prosecutors, as federal officials, should not be
subject to state court regulation of the bar.40 The prosecutors’ rhetoric was
sometimes heated and hyperbolic. For example, a 1991 press release jointly
issued by the DOJ, the National District Attorneys Association, and the National
Association of Attorneys General, accused the ABA of lending “aid and comfort”
to the defense bar in its “attempt[] to use rules of professional conduct to stymie
criminal investigations and prosecutions.”41
Although commentators tended to regard prosecutors’ anti-regulatory rhetoric as arrogant and extreme,42 they also recognized that there were legitimate
concerns to be raised about how ethics rules applied to prosecutors.43 For
instance, professional conduct rules did not necessarily take sufficiently into
account ways in which federal prosecutors’ work was different not only from that
of other lawyers but from that of state prosecutors as well.44 Professional conduct
rules and their disciplinary enforcement also raised some of the same concerns
that led the Supreme Court to hold prosecutors immune from civil rights liability
—e.g., a risk that prosecutors would become excessively cautious45 and that
external disciplinary proceedings would interfere with their work.46 Even if it
did not justify wholesale exemption from judicial oversight, respect for
prosecutors’ independence might be relevant to how generally applicable rules
were interpreted and what areas of professional conduct should be regulated.47
---40. See id. at 489 (“[The professional conduct rules forbidding communications with represented persons]
have in recent years been broadly interpreted by some defense counsel in an effort to prohibit communications
by law enforcement personnel with the target of a criminal investigation, whether or not a constitutional right to
counsel has attached. This expansive reading has been advanced in primarily two contexts, motions to suppress
evidence developed through such contacts, and disciplinary proceedings against individual Justice Department
attorneys at the state level. The effect of these efforts may someday be to achieve through [a professional
conduct rule] what cannot be achieved through the Constitution: a right to counsel at the investigative stage of a
proceeding. As a practical matter these efforts threaten to become a substantial burden on the law enforcement
process.”).
41. See Joint Press Release from the U.S. Dep’t of Justice, the Nat’l Ass’n of Att’ys General, and the Nat’l
District Att’ys Ass’n 1 (Aug. 6, 1991), quoted in John M. Burkoff, Prosecutorial Ethics: The Duty Not “To
Strike Foul Blows,” 53 U. PITT. L. REV. 271, 275 (1992). See also Showdown Over Standards of Conduct:
Prosecutors See ABA as “Arm of the Defense Bar,” LEGAL TIMES, Sept. 17, 1990 (quoting U.S. Deputy Attorney
General William P. Barr as stating, “[d]efense lawyers are using a professional trade association to try to undo
what the courts and state legislature have done to protect citizens from the criminal element”), quoted in
Prosecutors and the ABA, A Report to the President of the ABA by the Advisory Committee on the Prosecution
Function (Jan. 8, 1992) at p. 4 (on file with the author).
42. See Green, supra note 30, at 474-75 & nn.66-67 (citing discussions).
43. See Rory K. Little, Who Should Regulate the Ethics of Federal Prosecutors?, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 355
(1996).
44. See Zacharias & Green, supra note 7; see also Bradley T. Tennis, Note, Uniform Ethical Regulation of
Federal Prosecutors, 120 YALE L.J. 144 (2010).
45. See generally Zacharias & Green, supra note 12, at 39-41.
46. Id. at 43-46.
47. See, e.g., Massameno v. Statewide Grievance Comm., 663 A.2d 317, 336 (Conn. 1995) (observing that
“[t]here can be no doubt that ‘the doctrine of separation of powers requires judicial respect for the independence
of the prosecutor’” and that “[p]rosecutors have enormous discretion in deciding which citizens should be

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

881

Further, at least with respect to federal prosecutors, the DOJ had internal rules48
and an internal disciplinary process49 that arguably provided an adequate
substitute for external regulation in the form of rules and standards. In sum,
prosecutors might have perceived that they were special, that the ABA and
external judicial regulators did not sufficiently understand and take account of
their special role, that as public officials with a public-serving mission they were
particularly trustworthy to engage in self-regulation, and that internal guidelines,
supervision, training and enforcement sufficed, as proven by the presumed
propriety of prosecutorial conduct in areas, such as charging and plea bargaining,
that were largely exempt from external regulation.50
In the end, prosecutors mostly got their way, a result that might have reinforced the perception that regulatory institutions are sensitive to law enforcement
interests and deferential to prosecutors, but that might also have reinforced
prosecutors’ instinct that professional regulation was a battleground on which
they needed to fight to protect their turf. Few courts adopted the proposed
attorney subpoena rule or interpreted the no-contact rule or other rules to
meaningfully restrict prosecutors’ investigations. The ABA withdrew the controversial proposals to revise the Prosecution Function Standards.51 It also entered
into discussions of the no-contact rules with the DOJ, following which the
Association’s ethics committee issued an opinion concluding that the restriction
had more limited application in the context of criminal investigations than other
contexts.52 For a long time thereafter, the ABA refrained from adding new
provisions to Rule 3.8, even during the period when its Ethics 2000 Commission
comprehensively reviewed and revised the Model Rules.53
Moreover, the ABA attempted in various ways to address prosecutors’
concerns about regulatory capture. It appointed an advisory committee primarily
of prosecutors who documented “the growing tensions between prosecutors and

prosecuted and for what charges they are to be held accountable” and that therefore “in a particular grievance
proceeding, a prosecutor subject to investigation may be able to allege that, because of separation of powers
principles, different substantive or procedural rules apply to him or her than to the average attorney”) (quoting
United States v. Simpson, 927 F.2d 1088, 1091 (9th Cir. 1991)).
48. See U.S. Dep’t of Just. U.S. Attorneys’ Manual (2003). For discussion of some of these guidelines, see
Ellen S. Podgor, Department of Justice Guidelines: Balancing Discretionary Justice, 13 CORNELL J. L. & PUB.
POL’Y 167 (2004).
49. See Green, Policing Federal Prosecutors, supra note 7, at 84-87; Green, Regulating Federal
Prosecutors, supra note 7, at 156-57.
50. Cf. Bibas, supra note 92, at 964 (arguing that abuses of prosecutorial discretion should not be addressed
through external legal regulation but through internal, institutional solutions, including greater transparency and
improvements of office “structure, incentives, and culture”); Marc L. Miller & Ronald F. Wright, The Black
Box, 94 IOWA L. REV. 125, 161-66 (2008) (arguing that, even absent external controls, prosecutors can avoid
racial bias in charging decisions through “a highly structured and monitored office environment, with a
leadership committed to recording and reviewing the reasons for major choices”).
51. Sonner, supra note 38, at 1.
52. ABA Standing Comm. on Ethics and Prof’l Responsibility, Formal Op. 95-396 (1995).
53. See Green, supra note 4, at 574-75.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

882

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

the ABA”54 and followed up with a series of recommendations meant to
strengthen prosecutors’ voice in the Association and avoid “us[ing] the ethical
rules that govern the profession to establish rules of criminal procedure that are
more properly the province of judicial rulemaking or legislative action.”55 In
response, the ABA amended the bylaws of its Criminal Justice Section to ensure
that prosecutors and defense lawyers rotated as Chair and had equal voices
on its governing council, on which representatives of the National District
Attorneys Association, the National Association of Attorneys General, and the
U.S. Department of Justice were given permanent places.56 The Criminal Justice
Section now promotes itself as “the unified voice of criminal justice,” bringing
together and speaking on behalf of all the relevant stakeholders, including
prosecutors,57 and endeavors to address prosecution concerns no less than
those of the defense. For example, it recently spearheaded an ABA statement of
policy designed to address prosecutors’ concern about unfair harm to their
professional reputations from findings of prosecutorial misconduct that derive
from simple mistakes.58 Further, ABA positions on criminal defense tend to
be more balanced than those of representative defense organizations, in part,
because of prosecutors’ influence and in part because the Criminal Justice
Section’s leadership consciously strives for consensus among competing viewpoints.

II. THREE RECENT EXAMPLES
Prosecutors could have taken comfort in how the various professional conduct
controversies of the 1990s were eventually resolved. But recent events suggest
that the anti-regulatory rhetoric of that period lives on in today’s prosecutors’
offices and associations. Three examples are offered here: the first involves state
prosecutors’ opposition to an ABA interpretation of the rule governing prosecutors’ pretrial disclosures; the second concerns some state and federal prosecutors’
opposition to a rule directed at the rectification of wrongful convictions; and the
last regards a state prosecutor’s efforts to preempt a trial judge from examining
the ethical propriety of his office’s investigative conduct.

---54. Prosecutors and the ABA, A Report to the President of the ABA by the Advisory Committee on the
Prosecution Function (Jan. 8, 1992) at 3 (on file with the author).
55. Prosecutors and the ABA, Final Recommendations to the President of the ABA by the Advisory
Committee on the Prosecution Function (June 20, 1992) at 5-6, 9-10 (on file with the author).
56. See Janet Levine, Nothing’s Perfect, But the Brady Standards Could Easily Be Better, 26 CRIM. JUST. 1,
55 (Winter 2012); ABA CRIMINAL JUSTICE SECTION BYLAWS.
57. See ABA CRIMINAL JUSTICE SECTION, http://www.americanbar.org/groups/criminal_justice.html (last
visited June 3, 2012).
58. ABA Resolution 100B (Aug. 2010) (“RESOLVED, That the American Bar Association urges trial and
appellate courts, in criminal cases, when reviewing the conduct of prosecutors to differentiate between ‘error’
and ‘prosecutorial misconduct.’”).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

883

A. THE NDAA, THE ABA, AND MODEL RULE 3.8(D)

A window into some prosecutors’ attitudes toward professional regulation is
provided by the amicus brief recently filed in Smith v. Cain59 by the National
District Attorneys Association (“NDAA”)60 in response to one filed earlier in
the same case by the ABA.61 The Supreme Court was asked in the case whether
the New Orleans prosecutor’s office violated its constitutional disclosure
obligation under Brady v. Maryland 62 and its progeny63 when it failed to disclose
information that would have contradicted its witnesses’ trial testimony including,
among other things, a pretrial statement by the prosecution’s key eyewitness
stating that he could not identify any of the perpetrators.64 Although the state
argued that the withheld evidence was immaterial, it had an uphill battle—
indeed, one Justice asked in oral argument whether the state had considered just
confessing error65—and the state ultimately lost the case, with only Justice
Thomas dissenting.
The competing amicus briefs did not focus on the merits of the case but on
Rule 3.8(d) of the Model Rules of Professional Conduct,66 which establishes a
disclosure obligation analogous to Brady. Rule 3.8(d) requires a prosecutor to
disclose evidence and information that tends to negate the guilt of the accused,
unless the prosecutor obtains a protective order relieving the prosecution of this
obligation. The ABA Standards regarding the prosecution function include a
similar provision.67
Prosecutors’ violations of state ethics rules based on Rule 3.8(d) can result in
---59. 132 S. Ct. 627 (2012).
60. Brief for National District Attorneys Association as Amici Curiae Supporting Petitioner, Smith v. Cain,
132 S. Ct. 627 (2012) (No. 10-8145) [hereinafter NDAA Brief].
61. Brief for the American Bar Association as Amici Curiae Supporting Respondent, Smith v. Cain, 132 S.
Ct. 627 (2012) (No. 10-8145) [hereinafter ABA Brief]. During 2010-11, I chaired the ABA Criminal Justice
Section, which sponsored the ABA’s amicus brief in this case, and participated in discussions regarding the
brief’s development.
62. 373 U.S. 83 (1963).
63. E.g., Cone v. Bell, 556 U.S. 449 (2009); Strickler v. Greene, 527 U.S. 263 (1999); Kyles v. Whitley,
514 U.S. 419 (1995); United States v. Bagley, 473 U.S. 667 (1985).
64. Brief of the Petitioner at 3, Smith v. Cain, 132 S. Ct. 627 (2012) (No. 10-8145) [hereinafter Petitioner’s
Brief].
65. Transcript of Oral Argument at 20, Smith v. Cain, 132 S. Ct. 627 (2012) (No. 10-8145).
66. MODEL RULES R. 3.8(d) provides:
The prosecutor in a criminal case shall . . . make timely disclosure to the defense of all evidence or
information known to the prosecutor that tends to negate the guilt of the accused or mitigates the
offense, and, in connection with sentencing, disclose to the defense and to the tribunal all unprivileged
mitigating information known to the prosecutor, except when the prosecutor is relieved of this
responsibility by a protective order of the tribunal.
67. ABA STANDARDS FOR CRIMINAL JUSTICE, PROSECUTION FUNCTION, Standard 3-3.11(a) (3d ed. 1993) (“A
prosecutor should not intentionally fail to make timely disclosure to the defense, at the earliest feasible
opportunity, of the existence of all evidence or information which tends to negate the guilt of the accused or
mitigate the offense charged or which would tend to reduce the punishment of the accused.”).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

884

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

professional discipline but do not provide a basis for overturning a conviction.
Nonetheless, the Supreme Court had previously referred to Rule 3.8(d) and the
corresponding Standard in two opinions,68 recognizing that they are more
demanding than the constitutional obligation under Brady in at least one crucial
respect: whereas courts find Brady violations only when the prosecution failed to
disclose favorable evidence or information that was “material” to the defense—
i.e., that, in hindsight, might reasonably have produced an acquittal—the
disclosure requirement of Rule 3.8(d) demands broader disclosure.69 Model Rule
3.8(d) calls for prosecutors to make timely disclosure of all favorable evidence
and information known to the prosecutor, whether or not it is “material” in the
constitutional sense.70 Thus, a prosecutor could avoid close constitutional
questions of materiality by complying with the more demanding professional
standards.
In 2009, the ABA’s ethics committee, which periodically issues opinions
interpreting the Model Rules,71 published an opinion on Rule 3.8(d) reaffirming
the Supreme Court’s reading of the Rule,72 while acknowledging that, in a
handful of states, the counterpart to Model Rule 3.8(d) has been held to go no
farther than the constitutional imperative.73 As amicus in Smith, the ABA
refrained from weighing in on the merits, simply asking “that the Court again
---68. See Cone v. Bell, 556 U.S. 449, 470 n.15 (2009) (“Although the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment, as interpreted by Brady, only mandates the disclosure of material evidence, the obligation to
disclose evidence favorable to the defense may arise more broadly under a prosecutor’s ethical or statutory
obligations.”) (citing MODEL RULES, R. 3.8(d)); Kyles v. Whitley, 514 U.S. 419, 436-37 (1995) (observing that
Brady “requires less of the prosecution than” the ABA Standards).
69. ABA Standing Comm. On Ethics & Prof’l Responsibility, Formal Op. 09-454 (2009) [hereinafter ABA
Formal Op. 09-454] (“A prosecutor’s constitutional obligation extends only to favorable information that is
‘material,’ i.e., evidence and information likely to lead to an acquittal . . . . Rule 3.8(d) is more demanding than
the constitutional case law, in that it requires the disclosure of evidence or information favorable to the defense
without regard to the anticipated impact of the evidence or information on a trial’s outcome.”).
70. Id; see, e.g., 2 GEOFFREY C. HAZARD, JR. & W. WILLIAM HODES, THE LAW OF LAWYERING § 34-6 (3d ed.
2001 & Supp. 2009) Matter of Feland, 2012 ND 174; PETER A. JOY & KEVIN C. MCMUNIGAL, DO NO WRONG:
ETHICS FOR PROSECUTORS AND DEFENDERS 145 (ABA 2009); Bennett L. Gershman, Reflections on Brady v.
Maryland, 47 S. TEX. L. REV. 685, 691 n.28 (2005).
71. For discussions of the work of bar association ethics committees, see Ted Finman & Ted Schneyer,
The Role of Bar Association Ethics Opinions in Regulating Lawyer Conduct: A Critique of the Work of the ABA
Committee on Ethics and Professional Responsibility, 29 UCLA L. REV. 67 (1981); Bruce A. Green, Bar
Association Ethics Committees: Are They Broken?, 30 HOFSTRA L. REV. 731 (2002).
72. ABA Formal Op. 09-454, supra note 69. I was a member of the committee at the time it drafted and
adopted this opinion. For a discussion of the opinion, see Bruce A. Green, Prosecutors’ Ethical Duty of
Disclosure—In Memory of Fred Zacharias, 48 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 57 (2011).
73. The ABA brief acknowledged that there was national variation: one state, California, had not adopted a
rule patterned on Rule 3.8(d), although it was considering doing so, ABA Brief, supra note 61, at 8 n.14, and in
three jurisdictions—Colorado, the District of Columbia, and Ohio—prosecutors who comply with Brady
apparently are not subject to discipline under the corresponding state rule. Id. at 9 n.15. The ABA brief also
observed, however, that the Louisiana judiciary had adopted a version of the rule that was more demanding than
the Model Rule. Id. at 9-10. And it discussed the corresponding provision of the ABA Criminal Justice
Standards, which is virtually identical to Model Rule 3.8(d), and noted that the NDAA had adopted standards
containing a similar provision without a materiality requirement. Id. at 13 & n.18.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

885

make clear that a prosecutor’s pre-trial ethical disclosure obligations are
established by the attorney regulatory codes of the prosecutor’s state or
jurisdiction, and are separate from and broader than the constitutional standards
that control a court’s post-trial determination of Brady claims.”74
The NDAA’s amicus brief in Smith opposed that of the ABA. Although its brief
was nominally in support of the prosecution, its explicit purpose was not to
defend the particular prosecutor’s conduct, nor to argue for the lawfulness of the
defendant’s conviction, but rather to take issue with Rule 3.8(d), state counterparts, and the corresponding ABA Standard and with the processes and
institutions behind their development. Most significantly, the NDAA challenged
the very legitimacy of professional conduct rules insofar as they impose
obligations on prosecutors beyond those established by the Constitution, statutes,
or other law. The challenge was partly based on an exaggeration of the ABA’s
request: the NDAA portrayed the ABA as attempting “to persuade [the] Court to
grant their standards constitutional significance,”75 whereas the ABA was simply
asking the Court to remind prosecutors of their discovery obligations under
states’ professional conduct rules.76 Nonetheless, the NDAA correctly understood that if state analogues to Model Rule 3.8(d) were interpreted consistently
with their plain language, as the ABA urged, then those state rules would require
broader disclosure than the constitutional case law. A prosecutor’s violation of
such a rule would not provide a basis for an appellate court to overturn a
conviction, but a prosecutor at the trial stage would nonetheless be obligated to
comply with the rule and could be disciplined for deliberately failing to do so. In
this sense, the rule would “‘confer greater [discovery] rights to defendants than
the Constitution does,’” as the NDAA asserted.77
---74. ABA Brief, supra note 61, at 6; accord id. at 5. The ABA brief did point out, however, that if the
New Orleans prosecutors had complied with the state’s ethics rules and corresponding ABA and NDAA
standards, they would have turned over the evidence in question without regard to whether an appellate court
would later consider the evidence to be “material” to the defense. Id. at. 10, 14-25.
75. NDAA Brief, supra note 60, at 7. See also id. at 3 (referring to the ABA’s “proposal” that the Court
“adopt some sort of supplemental standard under the guise of the ABA’s proposed model ethics rules, that
would . . . bind prosecutors throughout the country”); id. at 17-18 (“This Court should not adopt [Rule 3.8(d)] as
some extra constitutional obligation”); id. at 19 (“The ABA should not be in the business of dictating to the
individual states or the federal government discovery policies and procedures that go beyond those adopted in a
comprehensive statutory scheme.”).
76. Nothing in the ABA’s brief suggested that the ABA’s Model Rules (as distinguished from state rules
based them) have any legal authority, that the state courts’ professional conduct rules might provide a ground for
overturning convictions, or that the Supreme Court had authority to interpret state professional conduct rules.
Rather, the ABA’s brief acknowledged that the Court’s decision would be based on decisions under the due
process clause, for which the ABA standards did not establish a baseline, ABA Brief, supra note 61, at 4, 6, and
which its brief did not address. Id. at 6 n.11. Although the ABA’s request that the Court make passing reference
to professional conduct rules may have seemed unusual, the Court had taken note of professional conduct rules
in prior opinions, see, e.g., Nix v. Whiteside, 475 U.S. 157 (1986); Jones v. Barnes, 463 U.S. 745 (1983);
including in opinions involving prosecutorial discovery. See cases cited supra note 68.
77. NDAA Brief, supra note 60, at 13 (quoting Ariz. Bar Op. 94-07).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

886

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

Although most professional conduct rules do not merely codify existing law,
the NDAA’s implicit premise was that state courts’ professional conduct rules
may not legitimately demand more from prosecutors than the Constitution
requires. Indeed, the brief suggested—albeit without elaboration—that it may be
unconstitutional for state court judges to adopt professional conduct rules
imposing additional obligations and restrictions on prosecutors, because such
rules may violate “‘the separation of powers doctrine’” or, in the case of federal
prosecutors, “‘the Supremacy Clause of the United States Constitution.’”78 In
other words, prosecutors, as executive branch officials, should be exempt from
state-court rules of professional conduct that do more than mirror preexisting
legal obligations.
In addition to questioning the legitimacy of independent professional obligations, the NDAA’s brief also challenged the legitimacy of the ABA’s role in their
development. It characterized the ABA as “a private organization that does not
speak for prosecutors,”79 an observation whose meaning and import is unclear.
The NDAA could not have been saying that the ABA excluded prosecutors as
members; however, it may have meant that, unlike the NDAA, the ABA does not
speak exclusively for prosecutors, or that it failed adequately to convey or take
into account prosecutors’ concerns. It portrayed the ABA as an advocate for
narrow, partisan interests80—“a left-wing lobbying group”81—in implied contrast to the NDAA, whose constituents are publicly elected or appointed officials.
The brief quoted the 1992 ABA advisory committee’s interim report which noted,
with concern, that many prosecutors perceive “that the ABA has become captive
to the narrow adversarial interests of the criminal defense bar.”82 The NDAA
implied both that prosecutors’ perception of the ABA twenty years ago was
accurate83 and that the perception persisted, despite the ABA’s subsequent
corrective measures, to which the brief made no reference.84
---78. Id. at 14 (quoting Ariz. Bar. Op. 94-07 (dissenting opinion)). The NDAA brief was quoting from
the dissenting opinion of a 1994 Arizona state bar ethics opinion. The committee’s opinion noted “the ethical
duty to disclose” under Model Rule 3.8(d), on which the state court’s rule was based, “is broader than the
constitutional due process obligation.” Ariz. Bar Op. 94-07 (1994) at n.3. The dissent took issue with the
committee insofar as it suggested that a state ethics rule for prosecutors might exceed constitutional obligations.
See also ABA Op. 09-454 (“The [Supreme Court] decisions establish a constitutional minimum but do not
purport to preclude jurisdictions from adopting more demanding disclosure obligations by statute, rule of
procedure, or rule of professional conduct.”).
79. NDAA Brief, supra note 60, at 3.
80. Id. at 4 (“[The ABA] is a private organization. The people of the United States have no voice in the
election of its officers or in the determination of its policies. While at times it has been given deference as the
voice of American’s lawyers, . . . the ABA has its own interests and its own agenda.”).
81. Id. at 5 (quoting Christopher Cox).
82. Id.
83. Even 20 years ago, the ABA would have disputed claims that it was doing the defense bar’s bidding, and
today, the characterization is belied by the Criminal Justice Section’s balanced leadership and its efforts to serve
as the legal profession’s “unified voice” on criminal justice issues. See infra at 881-82.
84. See NDAA Brief, supra note 60.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

887

Against this background, the NDAA sought to portray Model Rule 3.8(d)—
which had been adopted by the overwhelming majority of state courts—as
the product of the ABA’s partisan advocacy on behalf of criminal defense
interests. The Rule, in the group’s view, failed adequately to take account of
law enforcement interests in two respects. First, the NDAA argued that
compliance with the rule, as interpreted by the ABA, would impose an impossible
administrative burden on prosecutors.85 It did not explain why this claim was not
belied by various state laws and prosecutors’ office policies calling for “open file”
discovery, which is far broader than what the ABA Rule requires.86 Second, the
NDAA maintained that the Rule “fails to fully take into account factors . . .
such as the integrity of investigations and the safety of witnesses,”87 which, it
suggested, are better accommodated by the constitutional case law and statutes.88
The brief did not explain why this concern was not adequately addressed by the
Rule’s provision authorizing prosecutors to withhold favorable evidence pursuant to a protective order in unusual cases where disclosure might result in
obstruction of justice or threats to witnesses.89 Nor did it explain how the ABA
had managed to persuade the courts of virtually every state to adopt such a
supposedly unbalanced rule and why prosecutors had not opposed its adoption at
the time.90 Further, the brief failed to acknowledge that at the time of the events
of Smith v. Cain, the NDAA’s own disclosure standard “omit[ted] the constitutional standard’s materiality limitation.”91
---85. NDAA Brief, supra note 60, at 2. The brief’s reference to “the [impossible] burden” created by the
ABA echoes the Supreme Court’s reference in United States v. Bagley, 473 U.S. 667, 676 n.7 (1985), to the
“impossible burden on the prosecutor” that would result from a “[constitutional] rule that the prosecutor
commits error by any failure to disclose evidence favorable to the accused, no matter how insignificant.” The
reference overlooks a significant distinction between the Brady obligation and the obligation under provisions
based on Model Rule 3.8(d), namely, that the professional conduct rule requires prosecutors to disclose only
favorable evidence and information that they know, whereas the constitutional case law requires disclosure
of any materially favorable evidence in law enforcement agencies’ possession. While the professional conduct
rule is more demanding in one respect, it is substantially less demanding in another, namely, that it does not
require prosecutors to seek out information of which they are not already aware. See ABA Formal Op. 09-454,
supra note 69. In jurisdictions where prosecutors are required by law to make “open file” discovery, and other
jurisdictions where prosecutors do so as a matter of office policy or individual discretion, prosecutors routinely
provide more written information than the professional conduct rule requires.
86. See, e.g., Burke, supra note 13, at 2126-27; Robert P. Mosteller, Exculpatory Evidence, Ethics, and the
Road to the Disbarment of Mike Nifong: The Critical Importance of Full Open-File Discovery, 15 GEO. MASON
L. REV. 257 (2008).
87. NDAA Brief, supra note 60, at 4; accord id. at 18.
88. Id. at 18-19.
89. See MODEL RULES OF PROF’L CONDUCT R. 3.8(d) (1980); see ABA Op. 09-454, supra note 69.
90. For criticism of the processes leading to state courts’ adoption of these rules, see Green, supra note 72,
at 90-91.
91. ABA Formal Op. 09-454, supra note 69, at 5 n.22. See id., quoting NDAA, National Prosecution
Standards § 53.5 (2d ed. 1991) (“The prosecutor should disclose to the defense any material or information
within his actual knowledge and within his possession which tends to negate or reduce the guilt of the defendant
pertaining to the offense charged.”). This provision was subsequently eliminated in favor of one simply calling
on prosecutors to comply with their discovery obligations under the law. See NDAA, National Prosecution

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

888

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

Finally, the NDAA’s brief expressed apprehension about the disciplinary
process, and in particular about the possibility that disciplinary obligations
would lead defense lawyers “‘to threaten [prosecutors] with bar complaints’”
for failing to disclose favorable evidence, with the result that “‘[p]rosecutors will
be chilled by the thought of defending a bar complaint to the detriment of law
enforcement.’”92 The logic of this argument was that the state disciplinary
agencies to which state courts delegated authority to review grievances could
not be trusted to weed out defense lawyers’ unmeritorious complaints about
the inadequacy of prosecutors’ disclosures but would nevertheless require
prosecutors to respond to them; that defending against these complaints would
burden or distress prosecutors; and that prosecutors would therefore be overly
cautious (presumably by disclosing more evidence than required) to avoid
having to defend against baseless complaints. However, the brief pointed to no
evidence that over the past forty years, state rules had in fact led to either a glut
of complaints by defense lawyers or to excessive prophylactic disclosures by
prosecutors.93 Nor did it point to anything to counter the conventional assumption that defense lawyers under-report, rather than over-report, prosecutors’
misconduct in order to stay in prosecutors’ good graces for their own and future
clients’ benefit.
In the end, the Court issued a straightforward opinion holding that the
prosecution had withheld material evidence.94 Unsurprisingly, it did not refer one
way or the other to prosecutors’ ethical obligations. Whether the NDAA’s brief

Standards § 4-9.1 (3d ed. 2009) (“A prosecutor should, at all times, carry out his or her discovery obligations in
good faith and in a manner that furthers the goals of discovery, namely, to minimize surprise, afford the
opportunity for effective cross-examination, expedite trials, and meet the requirements of due process. To
further these objectives, the prosecutor should pursue the discovery of material information, and fully and
promptly comply with lawful discovery requests from defense counsel.”).
92. NDAA Brief, supra note 60, at 14 (quoting Ariz. Op. 94-07). The actual rarity of disciplinary
proceedings based on prosecutors’ alleged disclosure violations may largely be attributable to the enormous
time and administrative expense that they entail, as illustrated by a pending District of Columbia disciplinary
case in which a hearing committee recently recommended that a lawyer for the prosecution be publicly censured
for failing to disclose material, exculpatory evidence to the defense. Report and Recommendation of Hearing
Committee Number Nine, Matter of Kline, Bar Dkt. No. 522-09 (Mar. 28, 2012). The initial proceedings,
including two days of testimony, took a year from the filing of charges to the three-member committee’s
issuance of a 48-page opinion, which is reviewable first by the Board of Professional Responsibility and then by
the District of Columbia Court of Appeals. Bar Counsel will now have to contend not only with the respondent’s
arguments but with those of the government, which filed an amicus brief before the Board, challenging the
committee’s alternative finding that even if the evidence was not “material,” the prosecutor had to disclose in
because it was exculpatory. Brief and Appendices of Amicus Curiae United States of America in Support of
Respondent Andrew J. Kline, Matter of Kline, Bd. Dkt. No. 522-09 (June 7, 2012). Given the modesty of the
likely sanction for prosecutorial nondisclosures, the amount of effort needed to pursue these charges, and the
proliferation of more serious allegations against private lawyers, it seems unlikely that Bar Counsel would be
encouraged by success in Matter of Kline to pursue similar disciplinary charges in the future.
93. The implication may have been that, until now, no one took the state professional conduct rules seriously,
whereas that would change if the Supreme Court and other courts began to take notice of them.
94. See Smith v. Cain, 132 S. Ct. 627 (2012).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

889

discouraged the Court from alluding to prosecutors’ ethical duty, however, or
whether the Court simply saw no reason to do so, is unknown.95
B. STATE AND FEDERAL PROSECUTORS AND THE POST-CONVICTION
DISCLOSURE RULE

A second example of prosecutors’ anti-regulatory rhetoric is the reaction of
some prosecutors’ representatives to new state rules of professional conduct
based on ABA Model Rules 3.8(g) and 3.8(h).96 Sections (g) and (h) were added
to Model Rule 3.8 in 2008 to give meaning to prosecutors’ obligation to rectify
wrongful convictions.97 To some extent, they merely codify judicial pronouncements regarding prosecutors’ post-conviction obligations.98 For instance, Model
Rule 3.8(g) requires a prosecutor to disclose and investigate new evidence that is
---95. Why the NDAA decided to take a public, and seemingly gratuitous, swipe at the ABA, at a time when
the ABA was seeking to cultivate good relations with prosecutors and their national representatives, including
the NDAA, is also unclear. Conceivably, organizations representing subgroups such as prosecutors see a
political benefit to distinguishing themselves from a national organization of lawyers by demonstrating that they
alone speak for the unique interests of their constituency. But there are many specialty, as well as state and local,
bar associations representing subgroups of lawyers, and in general, they seek to work cooperatively with the
ABA.
96. MODEL RULES R. 3.8(g) provides:
(g) When a prosecutor knows of new, credible and material evidence creating a reasonable likelihood
that a convicted defendant did not commit an offense of which the defendant was convicted, the
prosecutor shall:
(1) promptly disclose that evidence to an appropriate court or authority, and
(2) if the conviction was obtained in the prosecutor’s jurisdiction,
(i) promptly disclose that evidence to the defendant unless a court authorizes delay, and
(ii) undertake further investigation, or make reasonable efforts to cause an investigation, to determine
whether the defendant was convicted of an offense that the defendant did not commit.
Rule 3.8(h) provides: “When a prosecutor knows of clear and convincing evidence establishing that a defendant
in the prosecutor’s jurisdiction was convicted of an offense that the defendant did not commit, the prosecutor
shall seek to remedy the conviction.”
97. See Stephen A. Saltzburg, Changes to Model Rules Impact Prosecutors, 23 CRIM. JUST. 1 (2008) (“The
additions to Rule 3.8 reflect the long-standing concern among prosecutors, defense counsel, judges, and
academics about the risk that any criminal justice system, even working at its best, may produce wrongful
convictions, and the importance of remedying such convictions in the face of important newly discovered
evidence.”). As Professor Salzburg’s column notes, I had a hand in the Rules’ development in my role, with
Professor Ellen Yaroshefsky, as co-chair of the Criminal Justice Section’s ethics committee.
For additional discussions of these provisions and their development, see ELLEN J. BENNETT ET AL.,
ANNOTATED MODEL RULES OF PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT 391 (7th ed. 2011); Wayne D. Garris, Jr., Current
Development, Model Rule of Professional Conduct 3.8: The ABA Takes a Stand against Wrongful Convictions,
22 GEO. J. LEGAL ETHICS 829 (2009); Niki Kuckes, The State of Rule 3.8: Prosecutorial Ethics Reform Since
Ethics 2000, 22 GEO. J. LEGAL ETHICS 427 (2009); Michele K. Mulhausen, Comment, Why States Should Adopt
ABA Model Rules of Professional Conduct 3.8(g) and (h), 81 U. COLO. L. Rev. 309 (2010).
98. See Bruce A. Green & Ellen Yaroshefsky, Prosecutorial Discretion and Post-Conviction Evidence of
Innocence, 6 OHIO ST. J. CRIM. L. 467, 471 & n.25 (2009) (citing authority); see also Warney v. Monroe County,
587 F.3d 113, 125 (2d Cir. 2009) (“The advocacy function of a prosecutor includes seeking exoneration and
confessing error to correct an erroneous conviction. Thus prosecutors are under a continuing ethical obligation

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

890

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

“material” and “credible” and that establishes “a reasonable likelihood” that a
convicted defendant is innocent. Model Rule 3.8(h) requires a prosecutor to
attempt to set aside a conviction if he obtains “clear and convincing evidence” of
the defendant’s innocence. The ABA adopted these provisions without controversy after extensive participation by prosecutors in their development99 and
regarded them as recognizing a modest—indeed minimal—set of obligations.100
So far, the courts of eight states, including Tennessee, Washington and
Wisconsin, have incorporated a version of one or both provisions into their rules
of professional conduct,101 and the NDAA has incorporated a comparable
provision into its own Standards.102
In some states, prosecutors’ institutional representatives have endorsed the
adoption of new provisions based on Model Rules 3.8(g) and (h). In Wisconsin,
for example, it was the state’s District Attorneys Association that initially
petitioned the state supreme court to adopt such provisions.103 Among other
things, the organization’s submission observed that prosecutors have a unique
role as “ministers of justice” and a duty “to seek justice” that sets them apart
from other lawyers. This distinctive duty makes most other professional conduct
rules, which are based on “the lawyer-client paradigm,” “minimally helpful” to

to disclose exculpatory information discovered post-conviction. Any narrower conception of a prosecutor’s role
would be truly alarming.”) (citing MODEL RULES R. 3.8(g) & (h)).
99. See Saltzburg, supra note 97.
100. See Green & Yaroshefsky, supra note 98, at 471-72.
101. The other states are Colorado, Delaware, Idaho, New York, and North Dakota. See ABA, CPR Policy
Implementation Committees Variety of the ABA Model Rules of Prof’l Conduct, R. 3.8(g), (h) (July 24, 2012),
www.americanbar.org/content/dam/aba/administrative/professional-responsibility/3_8_g_h.authcheckdam.
pdf. Additionally, the Arizona Supreme Court was recently petitioned to include the provisions; California’s
State Bar Board of Governors has incorporated the amendments in a set of proposed rules that it has submitted
to the California Supreme Court. The Arizona petition identifies and responds to five concerns raised by state
prosecutors. Petition of Larry Hammond and Keith Swisher at 5-10, In re Petition to Amend ER 3.8 of the Ariz.
Rules of Prof’l Conduct (Rule 42 of the Arizona Rules of Supreme Court) (Ariz. Sup. Ct. Nov. 1, 2011). Among
the concerns raised were that prosecutors were being singled out for a disclosure obligation when other lawyers
also encounter exculpatory information, id. at 7-8; that prosecutors do not need the rule, because they will take
action in any event when presented with strong evidence of innocence, id. at 9; and that the proposed obligations
seem inconsistent with existing law. Id.
102. NATIONAL DISTRICT ATTORNEYS ASSOCIATION, NATIONAL PROSECUTION STANDARDS 8-1.8 (3d ed. 2009):
When the prosecutor is satisfied that a convicted person is actually innocent, the prosecutor should
notify the appropriate court, unless the court authorizes a delay, in addition to the defense attorney,
or the defendant (if the defendant is not represented by counsel) and seek the release of the defendant
if incarcerated. If the prosecutor becomes aware of material and credible evidence which leads him
or her to reasonably believe a defendant may be innocent of a crime for which the defendant has been
convicted, the prosecutor should disclose, within a reasonable period of time, as circumstances
dictate, such evidence to the appropriate court and, unless the court authorizes a delay, to the defense
attorney or to the defendant, if the defendant is not represented by counsel.
103. Petition of Wisconsin District Att’ys Ass’n, In re the Amendment of Supreme Court Rules Chapter 20
Rules of Prof’l Conduct for Att’ys (Wis. Sup. Ct.).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

891

prosecutors.104 In particular, “by nature of the position, a prosecutor has a unique
role and special responsibility to rectify the wrongful conviction of an innocent
person.”105 By codifying this responsibility, the proposed provisions would
“protect the rights of criminal defendants who may have been wrongfully convicted and also protect the public by alerting authorities that the actual perpetrator
may still be at large,” and thereby “serve to increase public confidence in . . .
[the] criminal justice system.”106 Moreover, according to the Wisconsin prosecutors, the proposal was “consistent with prevailing policies and practices”107 and
“the overwhelming majority of prosecutors across the country have acted to
remedy wrongful convictions when they became known,” although “some have
not.”108 Similarly, in Tennessee, the state’s District Attorneys General Conference strongly supported the adoption of new provisions based on the ABA
models in order to “set[] a clear standard for prosecutors,” “increase confidence
in our criminal justice system,” and promote “a greater understanding of the
unique role of prosecutors to see the truth over and above winning a case.”109
As the post-conviction innocence rules’ endorsement by various state prosecutors reflects, one could hardly characterize these rules as an attack on
prosecutors or as an attempt to stymie criminal law enforcement efforts. These
provisions are very different from the no-contact rule, the attorney-subpoena
rule, and other rules over which prosecutors and defense lawyers had fought
several decades earlier. Those earlier rules, although serving other significant
objectives, generally impeded prosecutors’ ability to gather probative evidence
that promoted reliable verdicts. In contrast, Model Rule 3.8(g) and (h) promoted
the reliability of verdicts by calling for disclosure and investigation of important
new evidence that might establish the wrongfulness of a conviction.
Nonetheless, in several other states, prosecutors’ representatives vigorously
opposed the new provisions, not based on drafting preferences, but conceptually
and on a wholesale basis. For instance, in Washington, the Washington Association of Prosecuting Attorneys (“WAPA”) raised two concerns similar to those
---104. Id. at 1 & n.1.
105. Id. at 2; see also id. at 3 (“[T]he prosecutor’s duty to seek justice not only requires the prosecutor to take
precautions to avoid convicting innocent individuals but also requires action when it appears likely that an
innocent person was convicted.”).
106. Id. at 5.
107. Id.
108. Id. at 3.
109. Comments of the Tennessee District Attorneys General Conference at 2, In re: Petition for the Adoption
of Amended Tennessee Rules of Prof’l Conduct, No. M2009-00979-SC-RL1-RL, *2 (Tenn. Sup. Ct. Nov. 30,
2009); see also Lucian T. Pera, Proposed, Approved, Revealed . . . and Explained, 46 TENN. B.J. 12, 14 (2010)
(observing that “the [Tennessee] Supreme Court sided with the TBA [Tennessee Bar Association] and the
Tennessee District Attorneys Generals Conference, and rejected the position of the three incumbent United
States Attorneys” and that their “disagreement led to the most fascinating moment of the June 2010 oral
arguments on the TBA’s rules petition, when arguments on this proposal were made to the Supreme Court by a
veteran state prosecutor for the TBA and the DAs Conference and by a sitting U.S. Attorney in opposition”).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

892

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

in the NDAA’s amicus brief in Smith v. Cain.110 First, WAPA questioned the
legitimacy of state ethics rules’ expansion of prosecutors’ discovery obligations.
In a letter opposing the proposed post-conviction innocence rules, WAPA
characterized them as “an attempt to utilize the attorney disciplinary apparatus to
create new substantive rights . . . that defendants have not been able to achieve
[for themselves] through the courts or the legislature.”111
Unlike in Smith v. Cain, where prosecutors argued that constitutional disclosure obligations fully occupied the field, prosecutors suggested this time
that it was the constitution’s silence that precluded further regulation. WAPA
stressed that convicted defendants have no constitutional right to be told of
newly discovered exculpatory evidence,112 that “[n]either police nor prosecutors
have an obligation” under the law to investigate the possibility of a wrongful
conviction,113 and that convicted defendants have no right to court-appointed
counsel.114 Therefore, WAPA asserted, the effect of the proposed rule would be to
expand prosecutors’ obligations and defendants’ rights, which they argued was an
illegitimate role for a professional conduct rule.
The Washington prosecutors also expressed concern about “the Bar disciplinary process.”115 WAPA’s letter observed that “anyone can file a grievance
with the Bar Association” and predicted that the adoption of the proposed rules
“will trigger a significant number of grievances from convicted felons” that
will ultimately be dismissed.116 Like the NDAA’s amicus brief in Smith, WAPA’s
letter was implicitly questioning the fairness or competence of disciplinary
authorities, who prosecutors could not trust to weed out unworthy complaints.
In Tennessee, the three U.S. Attorneys, speaking jointly on behalf of the
DOJ, sounded similar alarms.117 First, they argued that the proposed rules
expanded on, or were inconsistent with, other law,118 and were therefore
illegitimate, and that the balance between defense and prosecution should be
---110. Letter of Thomas A. McBride, Executive Secretary, Washington Ass’n of Prosecuting Att’ys to Arthur
Lachman, Chair, Rules of Prof’l Conduct Comm. (Aug. 5, 2009).
111. Id. at 2.
112. Id. at 3 (citing Dist. Attorney’s Office for the 3d Judicial Dist. v. Osborne, 557 U.S. 52 (2009)).
113. Id. at 2.
114. Id. at 3.
115. Id. at 4.
116. Id.; see also id. at 5 (“[T]he real outcome of the proposed rule changes will be to increase grievances
and disciplinary litigation involving prosecuting attorneys without resulting in changes to the actual conviction
[sic] or a better measure of justice.”).
117. Memorandum of James R. Dedrick, United States Attorney, E.D. Tenn., et al., to Mike Catalano,
Clerk, Tenn. Appellate Courts, re: Objections to Adoption of Proposed Tenn. Rules 3.8(g) and (h) (Dec. 14,
2009).
118. They argued that the disclosure requirement may conflict with various confidentiality obligations
imposed on federal prosecutors by federal statute or criminal procedure rule, id. at p. 4, and that the requirement
that prosecutors investigate and seek to remedy wrongful convictions was inconsistent with state and federal
laws and rules that “allocate to the defendant the burden of investigating and raising claims of newly discovered
evidence.” Id. at 5.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

893

addressed by legislation, not by state court rules of professional conduct.119
Second, the federal prosecutors predicted that adopting the proposed rules
“would likely cause a flood of complaints from prisoners with time on their hands
and animosity toward prosecutors,”120 thereby diverting prosecutors “from
prosecuting crime to investigating convicts’ claims of ‘new’ evidence in order to
defend their law licenses.”121
The courts in Washington and Tennessee ultimately adopted versions of
the ABA models, and to date, there have been no reports from any of the six
states that have adopted rules based on Model Rules 3.8(g) and (h) that the
provisions have led to disciplinary complaints, administrative burdens or other
problems. Yet courts of other states have been slow to follow suit, no doubt
in part because of prosecutors’ opposition. The in terrorem effect of prosecutors’ hostility conceivably goes beyond discouraging courts from adopting
these particular rules; it discourages bar associations from promoting any
new ethics rules for prosecutors. In effect, prosecutors tell the bar, “If we can
stop courts from adopting provisions that codify what we all agree we should do,
imagine what a fight we will wage against something we really don’t like.”
Conceivably, that is the objective behind some prosecutors’ opposition.
C. QUEENS COUNTY PROSECUTORS AND TRIAL COURT OVERSIGHT

The final example involved the Queens County, New York District Attorney’s
unsuccessful effort to preempt a state trial judge from considering the propriety
of the prosecutor’s office’s conduct in interviewing arrested defendants before
arraignment.122
The story in brief is as follows:123 a defendant was arrested after a street fight
and, before his arraignment, he was interviewed on videotape by two prosecutors
---119. Id. (“Rule 3.8(g) and (h) are simply not designed to be compatible with existing laws and procedures,
altering the balance already struck in existing law without being subjected to the rigors of or accountability to a
formal legislative process.”); see also id. at 2 (“Proposed amendments based on Model Rule 3.8(g) and (h) are
likely meeting with a lack of acceptance because state bar disciplinary authorities . . . regard it as something
more appropriately addressed by legislatures.”).
120. Id.
121. Id. The prediction may seem to be at odds with prior experience. The federal prosecutors argued that
the proposed rules were unnecessary because prosecutors who suppress evidence of a convicted defendant’s
actual innocence are already subject to discipline for “engaging in conduct prejudicial to the administration
of justice.” Id. at 2 (citing TENN. RULE OF PROF’L CONDUCT R. 8.4(d)). But the federal prosecutors did not
point to any evidence that disgruntled prisoners were flooding disciplinary agencies with innocence claims
under existing disciplinary rules. Such claims would seem unlikely in any event, for a variety of reasons,
including that disciplinary agencies could be expected to dismiss them out of hand absent a prior judicial finding
of prosecutorial misconduct and because prisoners have little incentive to complain since the disciplinary
process could not afford them any relief. In any event, there have been no reports of floods of complaints in the
six states that have now adopted rules based on Model Rules 3.8(g) and (h).
122. Brown v. Blumenfeld, 930 N.Y.S.2d 610 (N.Y. App. Div. 2011).
123. The following facts are derived from the trial court’s submission in opposition to the District
Attorney’s petition. See Memorandum of Law of Respondent the Honorable Joel L. Blumenfeld in Opposition

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

894

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

and a detective. The interview was preceded by a series of scripted statements
and Miranda warnings.124 The defendant moved to suppress the statements he
made in the interview and, following a hearing, he argued that the interview had
been both unconstitutional and unethical. To help address the ethical question, the
trial judge deciding on the motion appointed a legal ethics professor with a
background in criminal practice125 to provide an opinion pursuant to the
procedure set out in the judicial code. The professor’s opinion concluded that the
prosecutors violated provisions of the state’s professional conduct rules in that
their script misleadingly implied that (a) the prosecutors and the detective were
disinterested, (b) there was an urgency and the defendant would gain an
advantage by speaking immediately, and (c) the defendant’s story would not be
investigated unless he immediately provided his account.
The District Attorney’s Office (“the DA” or “the Office”) moved to strike the
professor’s report as irrelevant to the question whether the defendant’s statements
were voluntary. The Office asserted that the professional conduct rules could not
be the basis of a suppression order because they “are not law” but “are largely
aspirational” and merely “provide guidance to the profession,” and that even
considering the ethical propriety of the Office’s interviewing practices “is wholly
misplaced . . . and highly prejudicial to the People.” The Office then filed a
lengthy legal memorandum with accompanying factual and expert submissions.
Ultimately, the trial judge refused to strike the independent expert’s report,
holding that ethics rules may be relevant to the suppression motion, and also
invited further briefing on the impact of a potentially applicable rule. Rather than
defending the Office’s interview policy before the trial court, however, the DA
filed a petition asking the intermediate appellate court to enjoin the trial judge
“from considering and ruling upon [the] alleged disciplinary rule violation” and
to strike the law professor’s expert report from the public record.
In part, the DA’s petition questioned trial courts’ authority to regulate the
conduct of prosecutors appearing before them, even though trial courts customarily oversee lawyers’ professional conduct pursuant to their supervisory authority
over both the proceedings and the attorneys appearing in them.126 In civil cases,

to the Petition, In re Brown v. Blumenfeld, Dkt. No. 2010-09688 (Nov. 19, 2010) [hereinafter Blumenfeld
Brief].
124. Among the statements were: “If your version of the events of that day is different from what we heard,
this is your opportunity to tell us your story. If there is something you would like us to investigate concerning
this incident, you must tell us now so we can look into it.”
125. The professor, Ellen Yaroshefsky of Cardozo Law School, was then chair of the ABA Criminal Justice
Section’s Committee on Ethics, Gideon and Professionalism. I had previously served with her as one of the
original co-chairs of that committee, and we have served as co-authors and in other professional collaborations.
126. For example, in rejecting the DA’s application, the appellate court noted that it is not “the only court
authorized to consider or make a finding with respect to whether an attorney has engaged in professional
misconduct” and that “trial-level courts often make such findings.” Brown v. Blumenfeld, 930 N.Y.S.2d at
617 n.5. In addition to defending his inquiry pursuant to the court’s supervisory authority over the conduct of
lawyers in the case before it, see Blumenfeld Brief, supra note 123, at 30, the trial judge noted that “New York

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

895

for example, trial courts often disqualify lawyers whose representation violates
conflict of interest standards and can impose sanctions, including disqualification
or suppression of evidence, for professional improprieties in gathering evidence.127 Further, trial courts regularly inquire into lawyers’ conduct sua sponte,
and are not limited to doing so in response to a motion.128 Nevertheless, the
DA characterized the trial court’s inquiry as overreaching,129 based, in part, on
separation of powers considerations.130
Further, the DA took the position that, in contrast to a disciplinary agency,
a trial court lacks the institutional competence to investigate and rule on a
prosecutor’s professional conduct and that such an inquiry would be unfair in at
least three respects.131 First, a judge who initiates an inquiry into a prosecutor’s
conduct is inherently biased because the judge is cast in the dual role of accuser
and arbiter.132 Second, suppression hearings do not afford prosecutors all the

courts have regularly examined ethical rules in determining whether a defendant’s statement should be
suppressed on constitutional grounds. Id. at 29, 35-39. Various bar associations and academics filed amicus
briefs in support of the trial court’s authority to inquire into the propriety of the prosecutors’ conduct on these
grounds. I was a signatory to one of those amicus briefs.
127. With regard to disqualification of lawyers for violating conflict of interest standards, see, e.g., GSI
Commerce Solutions, Inc. v. BabyCenter LLC, 618 F.3d 204 (2d Cir. 2010); Tekni-Plex, Inc. v. Meyner,
674 N.E.2d 663 (N.Y. 1996); see generally RICHARD E. FLAMM, LAWYER DISQUALIFICATION: CONFLICTS OF
INTEREST AND OTHER BASES (2003); Bruce A. Green, Conflicts of Interest in Litigation: The Judicial Role,
65 FORDHAM L. REV. 71 (1996). With regard to the imposition of sanctions for improprieties in evidence
gathering, see, e.g., Papanicolou v. Chase Manhattan Bank, N.A., 720 F. Supp. 1080 (S.D.N.Y. 1989); see
generally FLAMM, supra, at 282-302.
128. See, e.g., General Mill Supply Co. v. SCA Serv., Inc., 697 F.2d 704, 711-12 (6th Cir. 1982) (“[C]ourt[s]
should sua sponte raise ethical problems involving danger to a just, speedy, and inexpensive remedy, even if the
parties do not.”); Pa. Water Works Supply Co. v. Bucks Cnty. Bank & Trust Co., Civ. A. No. 91-2814, 1991 U.S.
Dist. LEXIS 11610, at *2 (E.D. Pa. 1991) (“[C]ourts allow the opposing party to raise conflicts of interest of
counsel, because of the need to uphold the integrity of the judicial process, and because the court, charged with
the responsibility of supervising the bar, has the authority, in any event, to raise ethical questions sua sponte.”).
129. Memorandum of Law of Richard A. Brown, District Attorney of Queens County, Brown v. Blumenfeld,
930 N.Y.S.2d 610 (N.Y. App. Div. 2011), at 23 [hereinafter Queens DA Memo] (“Judge Blumenfeld far
exceeded his authority in this case by improperly sua sponte expanding the scope of the suppression hearing . . .
[and] injecting the issue of the District Attorney’s ethics into the suppression motion before this had ever been
raised by the defense.”); id. at 26 (“[The judge] exceeded his authority by improperly expanding the scope of
defendant’s suppression hearing and assuming the role of an advocate at that hearing.”).
130. Id. at 35 n.18 (“A judge cannot give himself a ‘roving commission’ to determine whether a district
attorney has acted ethically or not [because] ‘each department should be free from interference, in the discharge
of its peculiar duties, by either of the others.’”) (quoting People ex rel. Burby v. Howland, 155 N.Y. 270, 282
(1898)).
131. Queens DA Memo., supra note 129, at 24 (the court’s inquiry occurs “in a forum in which [prosecutors]
have no opportunity for a fair investigation, hearing and determination by a competent authority, and no
possibility for appellate review of any such decision”). The District Attorney’s recognition of disciplinary
agencies’ authority to review the prosecutors’ conduct is somewhat inconsistent with the prosecutors’
suggestion that separation of powers considerations exempt the prosecutors’ conduct from judicial review and
wholly inconsistent with their suggestion in the trial court that professional conduct rules are not law, but are
aspirational.
132. Id. at 31 (“[The judge] transformed the simple suppression hearing pending before him into a shadow
grievance hearing, unconstrained by any procedural rules, where Judge Blumenfeld sits as both the accuser and

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

896

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

procedural rights or protections they would enjoy at a disciplinary hearing.133
Third, a finding of prosecutorial misconduct, unless it became the basis for a
suppression order, is not appealable.134 In addition to listing these three specific
inequitable results, the DA portrayed the inquiry into the prosecutors’ conduct
as itself an improper assault on their individual reputations.135 That is, the DA
implied that individual prosecutors would be irreparably harmed personally by
such an inquiry even if the trial court ultimately concluded that they acted
ethically. The DA failed to explain why this is so, and the answer is far from
obvious, given not only that the conduct would have been vindicated but that the
individual prosecutors would have been acting in accordance with their office’s
official policy guidelines. One might think that it was the reputation of the office
and the District Attorney that were principally at stake.136
Ultimately, the appellate court denied the “‘extraordinary remedy’” sought,137
noting that although trial courts do not have formal authority to discipline
lawyers for professional misconduct, they are authorized to consider and make
the Judge of the District Attorney’s conduct, and where the [prosecutors] are afforded none of the rights and
protections to which they should normally be entitled to defend against the very serious accusations levied
against them.”). The prosecutors pointed to the court’s appointment of a law professor to give an expert opinion
on the professional propriety of the prosecutors’ conduct as evidence of bias. Id. at 33 (The judge “did not solicit
or receive Prof. Yaroshefsky’s report for a proper purpose . . . , but, rather, because he wanted to insert an issue
into the case—and, worse, to do so from a particular vantage point, which was far from neutral”) (emphasis in
original). They reasoned, in part, that the professional conduct rules “are written to be plainly understood by all
lawyers so as to permit self-regulation” and therefore the judge “was more than capable of understanding the
law in this area without the assistance of expert advice.” Id. at 34 n.15.
133. See supra text accompanying note 132; Queens D.A. Memo., supra note 129, at 51 (“The rules that
govern professional conduct [establish] an appropriate forum and an established procedure for addressing
and deciding allegations of professional conduct,” and the appropriate “forum is not a suppression hearing; and
that procedure is not to have a hearing court solicit and rely upon conclusions of law of law professors, or other
alleged ‘experts.’”) (emphasis in original).
134. See supra text accompanying note 132. This argument is implicitly repudiated by the Ninth Circuit’s
recent decision in United States v. Lopez-Avila, 2012 U.S. App. LEXIS 2987 (Feb. 14, 2012), in which the court,
finding that the prosecutor engaged in impermissibly misleading conduct, named the prosecutor and remanded,
in part, for the trial court to determine whether to sanction her.
135. Queens DA Memo., supra note 129, at 24 (“The court’s past and impending actions . . . trample the
rights of the District Attorney and his Assistants to not have their integrity publicly and baselessly impugned.”);
id. at 51 (“Even entertaining the question of whether the People’s Central Booking Interview Program violates
the rules of ethics is . . . highly prejudicial . . . to all of the individual Assistant District Attorneys, personally,
who have conducted Central Booking interviews under the program.”) (emphasis in original); see also id. at 40
(stating that the judicial code provision allowing a judge to seek expert advice is not “a vehicle by which an
alleged ‘expert’ can unabashedly attack and impugn the integrity of a public official in a document that
automatically becomes part of the public record”) (emphasis in original).
136. The state district attorneys association filed an amicus brief supporting the District Attorney’s
application. Although adopting more restrained rhetoric, it joined in the argument that it was unfair to require
prosecutors “to defend against charges of misconduct or ethical violations in the context of a run-of-the-mill,
ordinarily non-appealable, suppression motion” because the context “denies a prosecuting attorney the
opportunity to fully defend against serious accusations of ethical breaches with no avenue of appellate review.”
Brief of Amicus Curiae Dist. Attorneys Ass’n of the State of N.Y., Brown v. Blumenfeld, A.D. # 2010-9688
(Dec. 13, 2010), at 8.
137. Brown v. Blumenfeld, 930 N.Y.S.2d 610 (N.Y. App. Div. 2011).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

897

findings “with respect to whether an attorney has engaged in professional
misconduct,” and, indeed, often do so.138 In this case, in particular, the propriety
of the prosecutor’s conduct was potentially relevant under state law to the
admissibility of the defendant’s confession.139 The appellate court acknowledged
that prosecutors were legitimately concerned about their reputations, and that
there was a possibility that the trial judge might make an erroneous determination
that could not be challenged on appeal,140 but held that these concerns were not
sufficient grounds to prevent the trial judge from reviewing and commenting on
the professional propriety of a lawyer’s conduct in a criminal case any more than
in a civil lawsuit.141

III. THE SIGNIFICANCE OF PROSECUTORS’ PUBLIC HOSTILITY
TOWARD PROFESSIONAL REGULATION
A. SOME OBSERVATIONS REGARDING PROSECUTORS’
ANTI-REGULATORY RHETORIC

Prosecutors, their offices, and their representatives do not have a single attitude
toward professional regulation and regulators. The conflicting responses to
Model Rules 3.8(g) and (h) make that clear. Like the prosecutors in the ABA
leadership who helped develop and endorse these provisions, the Tennessee and
Wisconsin state prosecutors’ associations saw as a good thing professional
conduct rules which codify the standards that prosecutors expect of themselves
and each other regarding rectifying wrongful convictions, because such rules
educate prosecutors and establish a positive prosecutorial culture. These associations evidently considered it beneficial to work with the organized bar to
develop provisions, based on the ABA models, that make sense for prosecutors in
their state, given its particular practices and procedures. The Washington state
prosecutors’ association and the Tennessee federal prosecutors, in contrast,
perceived the new provisions as threatening, and saw more benefit in opposing
them than in negotiating, compromising, or offering revisions that met their

---138. Id. at 617 n.5.
139. Id. at 618.
140. Id. at 618-19.
141. Having been freed to do so, on February 16, 2012, the trial judge conducted a hearing regarding the
ethical propriety of the prosecutors’ conduct. Daniel Wise, Suppression Hearing Takes Up Ethics of Practice in
Queens D.A. Office, N.Y.L.J., Feb. 22, 2012, at 1. On April 17, 2012, the trial judge issued a lengthy opinion
finding that the prosecution had engaged in improper conduct by falsely promising to investigate whatever
account the defendant provided. As a sanction, the judge ordered that the defendant’s post-arrest statement
could not be used in the prosecution’s direct case. People v. Perez, 2012 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 1767; 2012 NY Slip
Op 22103 (N.Y. Sup. Queens Cnty, Apr. 17, 2012). Less than two weeks later, the DA petitioned the appellate
court for an order barring enforcement to the trial court’s decision, and the court heard argument soon after.
Daniel Wise, Concerns Emerge in Argument About Ethics of D.A. Questioning, N.Y.J.J., June 25, 2012, at 1.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

898

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

concerns.142 The focus of this article is, of course, on the rhetoric of prosecutors,
like the latter, who express hostility to professional regulation. But it is important
to acknowledge that many prosecutors are not so hostile, and indeed welcome
constructive professional regulation.
In addressing the aspects of professional regulation in the three examples,
prosecutors were not functioning exclusively as advocates, and aside from the
Queens County scenario, they arguably were not functioning as advocates at
all. Prosecutors notably have other functions, including as “administrators of
justice” with a responsibility, as public officials, “to seek to reform and improve
the administration of criminal justice.”143 In these examples, prosecutors’ institutions were addressing how prosecutors should best be regulated, and as
public officials, their obligation was to promote the public interest, not personal
self-interest. The position of the Tennessee and Wisconsin state prosecutors’
associations, because it was so obviously contrary to prosecutors’ personal
interest in avoiding regulatory risk, comes across as an expression of the role of
disinterested “administrator of justice.” Of course, there is room for honest
disagreement about how best to serve the public interest, and prosecutors who
oppose regulation are not necessarily acting self-interestedly. But the less
plausible their anti-regulatory arguments seem, the more readily one views them
as abdicating their public-interested law-reform function.
For reasons suggested, although admittedly not fully developed, in Part II,
prosecutors’ anti-regulatory arguments seem implausible. Taken together, they
seem to convey that prosecutors should be immune from all external professional
conduct rules and their enforcement—that is to say, “we don’t need no regulation.” According to the prosecutors’ various submissions, professional conduct
rules cannot legitimately add to prosecutors’ preexisting legal obligations or
restrictions, and any new rule is simply an occasion for unwarranted complaints
by disgruntled criminal defendants. Even if professional conduct rules might
legitimately regulate them, prosecutors suggest, the existing process for developing professional conduct rules is illegitimate because of the influence of bar
associations, which are subject to capture by criminal defense interests. Further,
trial judges cannot undertake interpretation and enforcement of professional
conduct rules, because they are biased and their adjudications are unfair, but
disciplinary procedures also cannot be trusted to take adequate account of law
enforcement interests.
The anti-regulatory rhetoric in the three examples described in Part II was
largely inflammatory and superficial; it was not predicated on well-developed
arguments, but bordered on sloganeering. For example, some of the rhetoric
---142. Consequently, just as the positions taken by the ABA are unlikely to reflect the unanimous views of its
members, much less of all lawyers, the positions taken by prosecutors’ associations are unlikely to reflect the
full range of prosecutors’ views.
143. Prosecution Standards, supra n. 67, Standard 3-1.2(b) & (c).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

899

implied that professional conduct rules and interpretations of rules imposing new
obligations on prosecutors are invariably inconsistent with policy judgments
made by courts or legislatures, both when the courts and legislatures address an
area of conduct and when they are essentially silent. But the prosecutors making
those arguments did not explain why this was so in the particular cases, and there
is, of course, no reason why this invariably should be so. In general, the central
focus of professional conduct rules is different from that of substantive law, even
if rules and law may overlap. The Constitution, for example, generally sets forth
minimum obligations, and is not meant to preclude legislators from establishing
stricter rules. The same may be true of legislation as relates to ethical rules: the
former establish a floor, not a ceiling. Indeed, Congress’s adoption of the
McDade Amendment appears to presuppose that, at least as far as federal
prosecutors are concerned, ethics rules can and will establish additional
obligations. Thus, whether or not existing law reflects a policy judgment about
where lines should be drawn in the ethics realm cannot be established simply by
noting that law already exists on the subject.
Similarly, in its amicus brief in Smith, the NDAA never elaborated on its
suggestion that the ABA’s views on professional conduct are unworthy of respect
simply because the ABA is a private association. Given the ABA’s historic central
role in developing professional rules, and courts’ traditional reliance on the
organization’s suggestions, the NDAA’s dismissal of the ABA requires at least
some specific discussion of which of the ABA’s processes or attributes makes it
undeserving of continued influence. The mere fact that the ABA takes positions
that some prosecutors dislike does not mean that the organization is imbalanced,
much less that it is shilling for criminal defendants.
Besides being facile and inchoate, prosecutors’ arguments against professional
regulation were also indiscriminate and overbroad. For example, complaints that
courts and disciplinary agencies lack an adequate appreciation of law enforcement interests, or that new ethics rules will result in floods of burdensome
disciplinary complaints, can be invoked virtually whenever prosecutors would
be subject to any regulation at all via professional conduct rules.144 The logical
conclusion of these arguments, then, is that prosecutors should be wholly exempt
from professional conduct rules and from judicial oversight of their professional
conduct. Such a claim is hard to take seriously. Certainly, prosecutors do not
dispute that courts can adopt and enforce professional conduct rules restraining
prosecutors’ conduct in many respects, such as their arguments on summation
and their communications with the media.145 Thus, prosecutors should bear the
---144. See Zacharias & Green, supra note 7, at 39-40, 47-49 (discussing arguments that prosecutorial ethics
rules result in burdensome litigation, “that disciplinary regulators may lack the institutional competence to
evaluate and set standards for prosecutorial conduct” and that “disciplinary regulators [may lack] the authority
to impose standards inconsistent with prevailing law”).
145. See, e.g., MODEL RULES R. 3.4(e), 3.6 & 3.8(f).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

900

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

burden of explaining why courts should not undertake the particular regulatory
action at issue—e.g., what is wrong with a court’s adoption of a rule of conduct
on disclosure of exculpatory information or a trial court’s inquiry into arguably
misleading interrogation practices. To discharge this burden, prosecutors might
explain, for example, why a specific rule would intrude into an area where
prosecutors’ internal standards of conduct are particularly worthy of deference,
where courts are particularly unqualified to set standards, or in which a regulatory
inquiry would be particularly harmful. But the various submissions described in
Part II did not attempt any of this heavier lifting.
Ultimately, much of the prosecutorial rhetoric described above is not
convincing. For example, prosecutors have suggested that separation of powers
principles exempt them from professional regulation of prosecutorial conduct,
but courts reject this argument.146 State courts adopt rules specifically targeted at
prosecutors and (if only occasionally) they oversee disciplinary actions against
prosecutors on the obvious assumption that prosecutors, as lawyers, are subject to
regulation for professional misconduct. The U.S. Supreme Court made the same
assumption in its prosecutorial immunity decisions.147 In its extreme form, the
separation-of-powers argument would imply that courts cannot forbid prosecutors from suborning perjury, making false and misleading statements to the court,
or making improper jury arguments—a result that seems intuitively distasteful
and that no prosecutor has yet advocated.
Further, prosecutors have maintained that prosecutorial ethics provisions will
lead to burdensome disciplinary complaints but offered no empirical evidence to
support that view.148 Other arguments—casting prosecutors as potential victims
of an unsympathetic or unreliable judicial process—seem disingenuous, given
prosecutors’ customary role. For example, the Queens County prosecutors
sought extraordinary judicial relief from the perceived harm to their professional
---146. Of course, particular regulation may cross constitutional lines. See, e.g., Stern v. U.S. Dist. Court for
Dist. of Mass., 214 F.3d 4 (1st Cir. 2000) (finding adoption of attorney-subpoena rule ineffective, in part, on
separation of powers grounds); cf. United States v. Williams, 504 U.S. 36, 46 (1992) (noting limit on courts’
supervisory authority to restrict prosecutor’s investigative conduct in the grand jury, given grand jury’s
independence). For example, courts are deferential to prosecutors in the exercise of charging discretion and
would probably look skeptically at rules that encroach on that discretion. In other contexts, although not
exempting prosecutors from regulation, separation-of-powers concerns may be given weight in how prosecutors
are regulated. See, e.g., United States v. Basciano, 763 F. Supp. 2d 303, 314 n.7 (E.D.N.Y. 2011) (noting that
separation of powers concerns favor disqualifying an individual prosecutor rather than the entire office); United
States v. Koubriti, 305 F. Supp. 2d 723, 755-56 (E.D. Mich. 2003) (admonishing prosecutor but declining to
initiate criminal contempt proceedings for ethically impermissible public statements).
147. See supra note 10.
148. The problem with the prosecutors’ prediction that a particular standard of professional conduct will lead
to a flood of disciplinary complaints is that, as state courts adopt the standard, the prediction is tested. If the
prosecutors’ prediction fails, their credibility suffers. Cf. Bruce A. Green, Fear of the Unknown: Judicial Ethics
After Caperton, 60 SYRACUSE L. REV. 229 (2010) (arguing that the dissent’s prediction about the Court’s
decision would unleash a flood of recusal motions has been unfulfilled, and that public respect for the Court’s
deliberative processes may be undermined as a result).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

901

reputations from having to defend their professional conduct in a suppression
hearing. Yet prosecutors often show little concern for the reputations of individuals whom they accuse of criminal conduct in public filings, press
conferences, or elsewhere. Even when mistaken, they rarely take steps to repair
the reputations of those who are acquitted or against whom charges are not filed.
Likewise, prosecutors claim to worry that the risk of discipline will chill them in
performing their professional tasks, but discredit complaints about the chilling
effect of aggressive criminal prosecutions on others’ legitimate professional
activities.149
One might easily conclude that prosecutors’ employment of these arguments
against professional regulation is purely instrumental. Prosecutors’ customary
role is that of advocate, and advocates are entitled to make any non-frivolous
argument in support of their objectives. In the end, prosecutors’ opposition in
the three examples comes across as simply advocacy.150 In a different context,
if there were something to be gained by it, one can imagine prosecutors turning
about face and extolling the efficacy of the regulatory process. Indeed,
prosecutors recently did just that in Connick v. Thompson,151 where the New
Orleans district attorney’s office argued successfully that a wrongfully convicted
individual, who had been deprived of exculpatory evidence in violation of
Brady v. Maryland, could not predicate his civil rights action on the office’s
systematic failure to train prosecutors as to their discovery obligations. The
district attorney asserted that such training was in fact not necessary, because “[a]
district attorney reasonably relies on prosecutors obeying the standards of their
own profession.”152 An amicus brief filed by an association of New York state
prosecutors, elaborating on this point, approvingly cited both the state’s version
of Model Rule 3.8(d) and the counterpart ABA Standard153—essentially the same
provisions derogated by the NDAA’s brief in Smith v. Cain—and acknowledged
---149. See, e.g., Bruce A. Green, The Criminal Regulation of Lawyers, 67 FORDHAM L. REV. 327, 385 n.294
(1998) (noting that prosecutors complain about the chilling effect of disciplinary prosecutions but do not accept
at face value complaints that their prosecutions of lawyers will chill lawyers’ legitimate activities); Daniel C.
Richman, Federal Criminal Law, Congressional Delegation, and Enforcement Discretion, 46 UCLA L. REV.
757, 774 n.82 (1999) (noting that aggressive white collar prosecutions under such laws as “mail fraud, Hobbs
Act, money laundering statutes, and RICO” pose a risk of “chill[ing] legitimate economic activity”).
150. The apparent inconsistency of some of the arguments augments this appearance. For example,
prosecutors argue, on one hand, that rules codifying post-conviction obligations are unnecessary because
prosecutors already act consistently with the rules, but on the other hand, that such rules are unwarranted
because they establish obligations beyond preexisting legal ones.
151. 131 S. Ct. 1350 (2011).
152. Brief for Petitioner, Connick v. Thompson, No. 09-571, 2009 U.S. Briefs 571, 2010 U.S. S. Ct. Briefs
LEXIS 547, at *30 (June 20, 2010); accord id. at *38 (“Prosecutors are trained professionals, subject to a
licensing and ethical regime designed to reinforce their duties as officers of the court. Absent powerful evidence
to the contrary, a district attorney is entitled to rely on prosecutors’ adherence to these standards.”).
153. Brief of the District Attorneys Association of the State of New York as Amicus Curiae, Connick v.
Thompson, No. 09-571, 2009 U.S. Briefs 571, *10, 13, 2010 U.S. S. Ct. Briefs LEXIS 547, *15, 19 (June 11,
2010).

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

902

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

that both “ethically and in practice,” a prosecutor should disclose “all evidence
helpful to the defense,” not just material evidence.154
B. SOME CONCERNS WITH THE RHETORIC

There are many reasons to be concerned about the seemingly reflexive position
that some prosecutors’ representatives take in opposition to professional regulation. A principal concern is the potential impact of prosecutors’ arguments on
individual prosecutors’ attitudes and the culture of prosecutors’ offices.155 Given
the modest role of formal regulation, one cannot underestimate the importance
of maintaining an office culture that promotes prosecutors’ respect for, and
compliance with, legal and regulatory obligations and professional norms and
expectations.156 Even if anti-regulatory rhetoric is intended solely as an advocacy
tool, it is nevertheless likely to have a negative effect on prosecutorial cultures
in individual offices. To say that prosecutors employ anti-regulatory rhetoric
instrumentally is not to say that such advocacy has no influence on their systems
of belief. Prosecutors’ public rhetoric will necessarily enter their private
discourse. What they tell the courts becomes what they tell themselves and each
other, and they come to believe what they are saying. And, in this case, that can
foster perverse incentives and create a culture that is counterproductive to the
goal of being more ethical. For example, the Queens County DA’s attack on the
trial judge and the suppression hearing as biased and unfair is likely to be given
credence by assistant DAs in the office, with the result of eroding the office’s
respect for the court and its regulatory role. The derogation of provisions of
Model Rule 3.8 by the NDAA as the product of ABA partisanship both alienates
prosecutors from their professional peers and signals that professional conduct
rules are unworthy of respect. The suggestion that, as public officials, prosecutors
should be exempt from professional conduct rules both reflects and breeds
arrogance and indifference to prevailing professional norms as reflected in court
decisions and professional writings.
---154. Id., 2009 U.S. Briefs 571, *13, 2010 U.S. S. Ct. Briefs LEXIS 547, *19.
155. For a recent discussion of factors that have shaped a negative culture in the New Orleans prosecutor’s
office and the difficulty of improving the culture to promote compliance with disclosure obligations, see Ellen
Yaroshefsky, New Orleans Prosecutorial Disclosure in Practice After Connick v. Thompson, 25 GEO. J. LEGAL
ETHICS (9-3 2012). See also Ronald Wright & Marc Miller, The Screening/Bargaining Payoff, 55 STAN. L. REV.
29, 103-16 (2002) (exploring relationship between prosecutor’s screening and plea bargaining policies, office
culture, and election rhetoric).
156. See, e.g., Burke, supra note 13, at 2127 (recognizing the importance of “maintaining a system
and culture that values a fair process”). For other discussions of prosecutors’ office culture, see, e.g.,
Daniel S. Medwed, The Zeal Deal: Prosecutorial Resistance to Post-Conviction Claims of Innocence,
84 B.U. L. REV. 125, 132-50 (2004) (arguing that “the institutional culture of most prosecutors’ offices
values conviction rates and, in this environment, prosecutors may become wedded to maintaining convictions and resist incoming post-conviction motions based on innocence”); Abbe Smith, Can You Be a Good
Person and a Good Prosecutor?, 14 GEO. J. LEGAL ETHICS 355, 388-89 (2001); Zacharias & Green, supra
note 7, at 19.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

2012]

PROSECUTORS AND PROFESSIONAL REGULATION

903

Further, indiscriminate opposition to professional regulation is contrary to
prosecutors’ professional obligation to promote the positive development of the
law. Lawyers in general, as members of a self-regulating profession, are expected
to work to improve the law,157 and, as noted earlier, prosecutors in particular are
expected to do so as an aspect of their duty to seek justice.158 As public officials,
prosecutors should perceive a stake in promoting an effective professional
regulatory process and in promoting public respect for the process. Prosecutors
should therefore be circumspect about criticizing aspects of the process and
should confine their criticism to situations where it is truly deserved.
Prosecutors’ exaggerated opposition to professional regulation159 also undermines professional and public confidence in prosecutors. In the past decade,
there has been increasing public concern about the role of prosecutorial
misconduct in contributing to wrongful convictions.160 In this context, opposition to professional regulation seems tone deaf, and may prompt the public to
brand prosecutors as indifferent to the legitimate role of professional regulation
in promoting proper prosecutorial conduct and the importance of professionally
proper conduct to achieving just outcomes in criminal cases.
Finally, the breadth and nature of prosecutors’ arguments undermine their
credibility and detract from their more plausible arguments. For example, the
Queens County prosecutor’s attack on the trial judge and the adjudicative process
took away from his arguments that, at the end of the day, his office’s investigative
conduct was proper and not impermissibly misleading. Likewise, some prosecutors’ wholesale attack on proposed provisions based on Model Rules 3.8(g)
and (h) detracted from serious arguments that redrafting might be needed
to accommodate particular legitimate law enforcement concerns.161 If federal
prosecutors cannot support in principle a rule calling for disclosure of new and
credible evidence that creates a “reasonable likelihood” of a wrongful conviction,
what prosecutorial conduct rule would they support? Some prosecutors’ apparent
opposition to absolutely any new professional regulation may eventually lead
courts to discount even their legitimate reactions to proposed regulation.

---157. See MODEL RULES R. 6.1 cmt. 8 (pro bono rule “recognizes the value of lawyers engaging in activities
that improve the law, the legal system or the legal profession”); Chambliss & Green, supra note 18, at 425-27.
158. See ABA Standards for Criminal Justice: Prosecution Function Standards, Std. 3-1.2(d) (3d ed. 1993).
See generally Norman Lefstein, Excessive Public Defense Workloads: Are ABA Standards for Criminal Justice
Adequate?, 38 HASTINGS CONST. L.Q. 949, 977-78 (2011).
159. See, e.g., supra text accompanying notes 75-76 (noting NDAA’s mischaracterization of ABA’s
argument).
160. See, e.g., KATHLEEN M. RIDOLFI & MAURICE POSSLEY, PREVENTABLE ERROR: A REPORT ON PROSECUTORIAL MISCONDUCT IN CALIFORNIA 1997-2009 (2010); Peter A. Joy, The Relationship Between Prosecutorial
Misconduct and Wrongful Convictions: Shaping Remedies for a Broken System, 2006 WIS. L. REV. 399;
Editorial, Justice and Prosecutorial Misconduct, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 29, 2011, at A26.
161. See Saltzburg, supra note 97.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

904

THE GEORGETOWN JOURNAL OF LEGAL ETHICS

[Vol. 25:873

CONCLUSION
Twenty years ago, in the context of various battles over the application of
professional conduct rules to their investigative work, prosecutors expressed
reflexive mistrust of professional regulatory institutions. Many prosecutors
did not identify with the organized bar, and saw themselves as victims of a
pro-defendant regulatory regime in which the bar had significant influence.
Whether their mistrust was justified at the time is questionable. Even twenty
years ago, professional regulation posed little threat to prosecutors and imposed
no meaningful impediment to their legitimate work. Nevertheless, this negative attitude toward professional regulation by the organized bar—which has
little basis in reality—has persisted in shaping prosecutors’ rhetoric, although
the careers of most active prosecutors began well after the dust settled over
the regulatory battles of twenty years ago. During the careers of most active
prosecutors, the bench and bar have been highly deferential and, in the bar’s case,
inclusive. To the extent that prosecutors’ inflammatory anti-regulation rhetoric
reflects genuine belief, it seems likely that the belief is atavistic, vestigial,
unexamined, and shaped by the continued utility of exaggerated rhetoric as an
advocacy tool.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=2176252

 

 

The Habeas Citebook: Prosecutorial Misconduct Side
PLN Subscribe Now Ad 450x450
Disciplinary Self-Help Litigation Manual - Side